Incentive Compatibility and the Bargaining Problem By Roger B. Myerson



Yüklə 148,5 Kb.
tarix16.08.2018
ölçüsü148,5 Kb.
#63217


Incentive Compatibility and the Bargaining Problem

  • By Roger B. Myerson

  • Presented by Anshi Liang

  • lasnake@eecs


Outline of this presentation



Outline of this presentation

  • Introduction

  • Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • Response-Plan Equilibria

  • Incentive-Efficiency

  • The Bargaining Solution

  • Example



Introduction

  • Consider the problem of an arbitrator trying to select a collective choice for a group of individuals when he does not have complete information about their preferences and endowments.

  • The goal of this paper is to develop a unique solution to this arbitrator’s problem, based on the concept of incentive-compatibility and bargaining solution.



Introduction

  • Describe by a Bayesian collective choice problem:

  • (C, A1, A2, …, An, U1, U2, …, Un, P)

  • C is the set of choices or strategies available to the group;

  • Ai is the set of possible types for player i;

  • Ui is the utility function for player i such that Ui(c, a1, a2, …, an) is the payoff which player i would get if cЄC were chosen and if (a1, a2, …, an) were the true vector of player types;

  • P is the probability distribution such that P(a1, a2, …, an) is the probability that (a1, a2, …, an) is the true vector of types for all players.



Introduction

  • Assumptions:

  • a. C and all the Ai sets are nonempty finite sets;

  • The response of each player is communicated to the arbitrator confidentially and noncooperatively;

  • The arbitrator cannot compel a player to give the truthful response;

  • The arbitration is binding.



Introduction

  • Choice mechanism is a real-value function π with a domain of the form CX(S1XS2X…XSn)—for some collection of response sets S1, S2,…, Sn—such that

  • ∑c,ЄCπ(c’|s1,…,sn)=1, and π(c|s1,…,sn) for all c,for every (s1,…,sn) in S1XS2X…XSn.

  • Ai is the standard response set.



Outline of this presentation

  • Introduction

  • Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • Response-Plan Equilibria

  • Incentive-Efficiency

  • The Bargaining Solution

  • Example



Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • With a choice mechanism π, we have Zi(π, bi|ai) represents the conditionally-expected utility payoff for player i, here ai is his true type, bi is the type he claims.

  • A choice mechanism is Bayesian incentive-compatible if

  • Zi(π, ai|ai)≥ Zi(π, bi|ai) for all i, aiЄAi, biЄAi



Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • Define Vi(π|ai)=Zi(π, ai|ai) if choice mechanism π is used and if everyone is honest.

  • Define V(π)=((Vi(π|ai))a1ЄA1,…,(Vn(π|an)) anЄAn).

  • The feasible set of expected allocation vectors:

  • F={V(π): π is a choice mechanism}

  • The incentive-feasible set of expected allocation vectors:

  • F*={V(π): π is a Bayesian incentive-compatible}



Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • Theorem 1: F* is a nonempty convex and compact subset of F (proof in the paper).

  • If Vi(π|ai)for all i and aiЄAi, we say that π is strictly dominated by π’.



Outline of this presentation

  • Introduction

  • Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • Response-Plan Equilibria

  • Incentive-Efficiency

  • The Bargaining Solution

  • Example



Response-Plan Equilibria

  • A response plan for player i is a function σi mapping each type aiЄAi onto a probability distribution over his response set Si. σi(si|ai) is the probability that player i will tell the arbitrator si if his true type is ai

  • So we have Wi(π, σ1, …, σn|ai) to represent the player i’s expected utility payoff; similarly to before, we have a vector of conditionally-expected payoffs:

  • W(π, σ1, …, σn)=(((Wi(π, σ1, …, σn|ai))aiЄAi)ni=1)



Response-Plan Equilibria

  • (σ1, …, σn) is a response-plan equilibrium for the choice mechanism π if, for any player i and type aiЄAi, for every possible alternative response plan σ’i for player i:

  • Wi(π, σ1, …, σn|ai)≥ Wi(π, σ1, …, σi-1, σ’i, σi+1,…,σn|ai)

  • The equilibrium-feasible set of expected allocation vectors:

  • F**={W(π, σ1, …, σn): π is a choice mechanism, and (σ1, …, σn) is a response-plan equilibrium for π}

  • Theorem 2: F**=F* (proof in the paper)



Outline of this presentation

  • Introduction

  • Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • Response-Plan Equilibria

  • Incentive-Efficiency

  • The Bargaining Solution

  • Example



Incentive-Efficiency

  • π is incentive-efficient if and only if it is a Bayesian incentive-compatible choice mechanism and is not strictly dominated by any other Bayesian incentive-compatible mechanism (remind: If Vi(π|ai)for all i and aiЄAi, we say that π is strictly dominated by π’).



Outline of this presentation

  • Introduction

  • Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • Response-Plan Equilibria

  • Incentive-Efficiency

  • The Bargaining Solution

  • Example



The Bargaining Solution

  • Conflict outcome: it represents what would happen by default if the arbitrator failed to lead the players to an agreement. Examples:

  • Market

  • Politics

  • Students

  • Conflict payoff vector:

  • t=((ta1)a1ЄA1, (ta2)a2ЄA2,…,(tan)anЄAn), where each tai is player i’s conditional expectation, given that ai is his true type, of what his utility payoff would be if the conflict outcome occurred.



The Bargaining Solution

  • Given the conflict payoff vector t our collective choice problem becomes a bargaining problem, with a feasible set F*, t is a reference point in F*.

  • Let F*+ be the set of all incentive-feasible payoff vectors which are individually rational:

  • F*+=F*∩{y:yai≥tai for all i and all aiЄAi}

  • Theorem 3: Suppose that c* is not incentive-efficient, then there exist a unique incentive-feasible bargaining solution.



Outline of this presentation

  • Introduction

  • Bayesian Incentive-Compatibility

  • Response-Plan Equilibria

  • Incentive-Efficiency

  • The Bargaining Solution

  • Example



Example

  • Two players share the cost of a project which benefit them both.

  • The project cost $100, the two players call an arbitrator to divide it.

  • Project value:

  • Player1: $90 if he is type1.0, $30 if he is type1.1

  • Player2: $90

  • 4. To the arbitrator and player2, P1(1.0)=.9 and P2(1.1)=.1



Example

  • Some observation points:

  • No matter what player 1’s type is, the project appears to be worth more than it costs;

  • The decisions cannot be made separately.

  • Some intuitive solutions:

  • 50-50 or 20-80

  • 47-53

  • 50-50 or 0-0



Example

  • Formal solution:

  • Let C={c0, c1, c2}, A1={1.0, 1.1}, A2={2}. We have P(1.0, 2)=.9 and P(1.1, 2) =.1.

  • c0 means do not undertake the project”; c1 means “undertake the project and make player1 pay for it”; c2 means “undertake the project and make player2 pay for it”.



Example

  • Strategies can be randomized.

  • Use the abbreviations π0j=π(cj|1.0, 2) and π1j=π(cj|1.1, 2).

  • The incentive-compatible choice mechanisms satisfies the following:

  • -10π01+90π02≥-10π11+90π12,

  • -70π11+30π12≥-10π01+90π02,

  • π00+π01+π02=1, π10+π11+π12=1

  • ,



Example

  • Expected benefits for all players:

  • x1.0=0π00-10π01+π02,

  • x1.1=0π10-10π11+π12,

  • x2=.9(0π00+90π01-10π02)+.1(0π10+90π11-10π12),

  • Then the incentive-feasible bargaining solution is the solution that maximize

  • ((x1.0).9(x1.1).1x2), x and π satisfy the restrictions above.



Example

  • Result:

  • x1.0=39.5, x1.1=13.2, x2=36

  • π01=.505, π02=.495, π10=.561 and π12=.439

  • Meanings in English



Conclusion

  • A great paper overall

  • The mathematical derivation is complicated but very clear

  • This concept can be possibly extended to our networking study. For example, say that the arbitrator is the network designer; the two players are network users, etc.



Thank you very much!

  • Anshi Liang



Yüklə 148,5 Kb.

Dostları ilə paylaş:




Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©genderi.org 2024
rəhbərliyinə müraciət

    Ana səhifə