John Stuart Mill and the Liberty of Inebriation



Yüklə 0,56 Mb.
Pdf görüntüsü
tarix25.07.2018
ölçüsü0,56 Mb.
#58554


Subscribe to 

The Independent Review

 and receive a 

free book of your choice* such as the 25th Anniversary 

Edition of 



Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the 

Growth of American Government, by Founding Editor 

Robert Higgs. This quarterly journal, guided by co-editors 

Christopher J. Coyne, and Michael C. Munger, and Robert 

M. Whaples offers leading-edge insights on today’s most 

critical issues in economics, healthcare, education, law, 

history, political science, philosophy, and sociology.  

Thought-provoking and educational, 

The Independent 

Review

 is blazing the way toward informed debate!

Student? Educator? Journalist? Business or civic leader? 

Engaged citizen? This journal is for YOU!

INDEPENDENT INSTITUTE, 100 SWAN WAY, OAKLAND, CA 94621 • 800-927-8733 • REVIEW@INDEPENDENT.ORG   

PROMO CODE IRA1703



SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE 

CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* 

FREE!

*

Order today for more FREE book options

Perfect for students or anyone on 

the go! 

The Independent Review is 

available on mobile devices or tablets: 

iOS devices, Amazon Kindle Fire, or 

Android through Magzter.



The Independent Review does not accept 

pronouncements of government officials nor the 

conventional wisdom at face value.”



JOHN R. MACARTHUR, Publisher, Harper’s



The Independent Review is 

excellent.”



GARY BECKER, Noble Laureate 

in Economic Sciences




253

John Stuart Mill

and the Liberty

of Inebriation

——————

✦   ——————



R

ICHARD


G

LEN


B

OIRE


A

s an important nineteenth or twentieth century work on political and social

theory, John Stuart Mill’s essay On Liberty (

͓1859͔ 1975) is considered to be

second only to the Communist Manifesto. Written in the midst of the grow-

ing political power of Christian temperance groups pushing for alcohol prohibition

and speaking directly to the issue of the rights of individuals and the limits of author-

itarian control, On Liberty is a seminal antiprohibition text, which assumes ever

greater importance and relevance when considered in the context of today’s $19 bil-

lion “war on drugs.”

Drafted in the tumult of the first societal debates over alcohol prohibition, Mill’s

essay examines “the nature and limits of the power which can be legitimately exercised

by society over the individual” (3) and is one of the earliest political statements against

drug prohibition as well as a vindication of cognitive liberty. On Liberty was published

in 1859 but was penned in 1855, only four years after the state of Maine enacted the

first law in the United States prohibiting the sale of alcohol, an action that kicked off

a wave of prohibition laws in the country. By 1855, thirteen states had passed alcohol

prohibition laws, and the American Temperance Society had long since shifted from a

call for “temperance” to a demand for wholesale prohibition. In England, where Mill

wrote, the United Kingdom Alliance of Legislative Suppression of the Sale of Intoxi-

cating Liquors sprang up in 1853, and it used the Maine law as a model in pushing for

alcohol prohibition in England. Thus, it is not surprising that Mill’s consideration of



The Independent Review, v.VII, n.2, Fall 2002, ISSN 1086-1653, Copyright © 2002, pp. 253– 258.

Richard Glen Boire

is the executive director of the Center for Cognitive Liberty and Ethics in Davis, Cal-

ifornia.



T

HE

I



NDEPENDENT

R

EVIEW



254

R



I C H A R D

G

L E N



B

O I R E


the rights of individuals vis-à-vis society and the government, forged in the midst of

such heated social controversy,  would confront directly the important question of

cognitive liberty.

“The object of this Essay,” wrote Mill, “ is to assert one very simple principle . . .

that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in

interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection . . . 

͓that

is

͔ to prevent harm to others” (10–11). Government interference, wrote Mill, is



appropriate only when a person engages in conduct that threatens the interests of oth-

ers. What happens inside a person’s body or mind is that person’s private business, not

the business of society and certainly not the business of the government. He expressed

this point unambiguously: “Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individ-

ual is sovereign” (11).

So long as a person’s decision and subsequent conduct did not threaten others

with harm, Mill considered the person’s action to lie within a protected “region of

human liberty” (13). Encompassed within this domain of liberty is:

the inward domain of consciousness; demanding liberty of thought and

feeling, absolute freedom of opinion and sentiment on all subjects, practi-

cal or speculative, scientific, moral, or theological . . . liberty of tastes and

pursuits; of framing the plan of our life to suit our own character; of doing

as we like, subject to such consequences as may follow: without impedi-

ment from our fellow-creatures, so long as what we do does not harm

them, even though they should think our conduct foolish, perverse, or

wrong. (13)

For Mill, a society that refuses to recognize and respect this sphere of liberty is

not a free society, and laws that invade this province are unjustifiable; freedom

demands this protected domain. “The only freedom which deserves the name,” writes

Mill, “is that of pursuing our own good in our own way, so long as we do not attempt

to deprive others of theirs, or impede their efforts to obtain it” (14).

Mill was quick to emphasize that these principles apply only to adults. Children,

while they are still under the care of an adult, “must be protected against their own

actions as well as against external injury” (12), and it is therefore appropriate for soci-

ety or the government to act paternalistically toward them. Mill also acknowledges

and repeatedly underscores that when a person’s behavior does directly affect other

people, it is, by its very nature, social conduct and thus becomes an appropriate object

for social and government control.

The roots of alcohol prohibition grew out of Protestant Christianity. In 1832,

James Teare, founder of the Preston General Temperance Society in England, was

speaking for many temperance advocates of the time when he took the floor at a tem-

perance meeting in Manchester and declared all intoxicating liquor anathema to reli-

gious people: “the sooner it is put out of this world, the better” (qtd. in Inglis 1975,



V

OLUME


VII, N

UMBER


2, F

ALL


2002

J

O H N



S

T U A R T

M

I L L A N D T H E



L

I B E R T Y O F

I

N E B R I AT I O N



255


137). Not surprisingly, therefore, woven throughout On Liberty are subtle and not so

subtle jabs at both the timidity (“essentially a doctrine of passive obedience” 

͓48͔) and

the coerciveness of Christianity. Religion, says Mill, is an “engine of moral repression”

(14), seeking “control over every department of human conduct” (14). In some of

his harshest words, Mill admonishes:

Christian morality (so called) has all the characters of a reaction; it is, in

great part, a protest against Paganism. Its ideal is negative rather than pos-

itive; passive rather than active; Innocence rather than Nobleness; Absti-

nence from Evil, rather than energetic Pursuit of Good: in its precepts (as

has been well said) “thou shalt not” predominates unduly over “thou

shalt.” In its horror of sensuality, it made an idol of asceticism, which has

been gradually compromised away into one of legality. (47–48)

Mill’s objection to the Christianity of the mid–nineteenth century fundamentally was

to its complete capitulation to authority, coupled with its all-encompassing dogma-

tism and a singular way of conceiving of the world. These latter traits, Mill believed,

often led its followers to suppress eccentricity, individuality, original thought, and

simple pleasures.



On Liberty champions responsible alcohol inebriation as a private pleasure,

which the government has no authority to interfere with as long as the drinker is not

harming another person. Provided that a person’s conduct does not affect the inter-

ests of other people, writes Mill, that person should have “perfect freedom, legal and

social, to do the action and stand the consequences” (70).

Mill rejects challenges that assert that a person’s actions inherently have some

effect on society or that an act that harms the individual also harms society. Mill

responds to these challenges on two levels. First, he acknowledges that if a person’s

“self-regarding” conduct disables him from performing some public duty or produces

identifiable harm to another person, then that conduct properly cannot be considered

“self-regarding,” and society may control or punish the person. Using alcohol intox-

ication as an example, Mill explains: “No person ought to be punished simply for

being drunk; but a soldier or a policeman should be punished for being drunk on

duty. Whenever, in short, there is a definite damage, or a definite risk of damage,

either to an individual or to the public, the case is taken out of the province of liberty,

and placed in that of morality or law” (76). To the extent that the “harm” to others

from drinking alcohol is amorphous or that the drinker violates no specific duty, Mill

views the ancillary “harm” from the drinker’s action as an “inconvenience . . . which

society can afford to bear, for the sake of the greater good of human freedom” (76).

In essence, Mill views the temperance challenge as embodying a Puritanical per-

spective that considers innumerable self-regarding actions to be morally wrong and

thus inherently injurious to the society. He rejects this position as religious moraliz-

ing cloaked in claims for social policy. As an example, he quotes the secretary of the



T

HE

I



NDEPENDENT

R

EVIEW



256

R



I C H A R D

G

L E N



B

O I R E


United Kingdom Alliance for the Legislative Suppression of the Sale of Intoxicating

Liquors, who wrote:

If anything invades my social rights, certainly the traffic in strong drink

does. It destroys my primary right of security, by constantly creating and

stimulating social disorder. It invades my right of equality, by deriving a

profit from the creation of a misery I am taxed to support. It impedes my

right to free moral and intellectual development, by surrounding my path

with dangers, and by weakening and demoralizing society, from which I

have a right to claim mutual aid and intercourse. (83)

Mill calls the secretary’s definition of social rights a “monstrous principle” (83) that,

if accepted, would vitiate the meaning of liberty entirely: “there is no violation of lib-

erty which it would not justify; it acknowledges no right to any freedom whatever. . . .

The doctrine ascribes to all mankind a vested interest in each other’s moral, intellec-

tual, and even physical perfection, to be defined by each claimant according to his

own standard” (84).

Although Mill is perfectly capable of presenting his argument in theoretical

terms, he turns his attention to what he calls “gross usurpations upon the liberty of

private life actually practiced” (82) and without equivocation responds to efforts

under way at that time to prohibit the drinking of alcohol:

Under the name of preventing intemperance, the people of one English

colony, and of nearly half the United States, have been interdicted by law

from making any use whatever of fermented drinks, except for medical pur-

poses: for prohibition of their sale is in fact, as it is intended to be, prohibi-

tion of their use. And though the impracticability of executing the law has

caused its repeal in several of the States which had adopted it . . . an attempt

has notwithstanding been commenced, and is prosecuted with considerable

zeal by many of the professed philanthropists, to agitate for a similar law in

this country. (82–83)

Mill acknowledges that selling alcohol is a social act because it inherently involves a

buyer and a seller, but, as he notes, the underlying aim of the laws that prohibit sales

of alcohol is to squelch the use of alcohol. “

͓T͔he infringement complained of is not

on the liberty of the seller,” notes Mill, “but on that of the buyer and consumer; since

the state might just as well forbid him to drink wine as purposely make it impossible

for him to obtain it” (83). Mill remarks that when a “trade law” has the effect of pro-

hibiting a commodity, it is really a prohibition law in disguise.

Similarly, Mill is skeptical of so-called sin taxes, which artificially inflate the price

of a product in order to discourage its use. Such a tax, he explains, “is a prohibition,

to those whose means do not come up to the augmented price; and to those who do,

it is a penalty laid on them for gratifying a particular taste” (93). A person’s “choice




V

OLUME


VII, N

UMBER


2, F

ALL


2002

J

O H N



S

T U A R T

M

I L L A N D T H E



L

I B E R T Y O F

I

N E B R I AT I O N



257


of pleasures,” writes Mill, ought to be each person’s  “own concern, and must rest

with 


͓his͔ own judgment” (93). Ultimately, however, Mill would permit a special tax

on products such as alcohol, but only to the extent that the tax increased revenue for

the government. A “sin tax” would be inappropriate if set so high that it actually dis-

suaded a sufficient number of buyers so as to result in a decrease in total tax revenues

from sales of the product.

With respect to items that can be abused, such as “poisons,” Mill notes that

“there is hardly any part of the legitimate form of action of a human being which

would not admit of being represented, and fairly too, as increasing the facilities for

some form or other of delinquency” (89). Thus, if a person desires to purchase a poi-

son, it is inappropriate for the government to enjoin the purchase merely because the

person might abuse the poison or use it to commit a crime. Instead, the laws should

stop after requiring that drugs and poisons be labeled with cautionary statements.

Mill does not believe that doctors should be the gatekeepers to drugs, noting that

͓t͔o require in all cases the certificate of a medical practitioner would make it some-



times impossible, always expensive, to obtain the article for legitimate uses” (90). At

most, any adults who wish to purchase such an item may be required to register their

name, address, and an explanation of why they are purchasing a particular item.

Although Mill firmly believes it would be an illegitimate use of power for the

government to prohibit inebriation based on a inchoate concern that an inebriated

person might cause harm to others, he reasonably concedes that if an inebriated per-

son does harm another person, then the government rightfully may prohibit that per-

son from becoming inebriated in the future. “Drunkenness,” Mill explains, “in ordi-

nary cases, is not a fit subject for legislative interference; but I should deem it perfectly

legitimate that a person, who had once been convicted of any act of violence to oth-

ers under the influence of drink, should be placed under a special legal restriction, per-

sonal to himself; that if he were afterwards found drunk, he should be liable to a

penalty. . . . The making himself drunk, in a person whom drunkenness excites to do

harm to others, is a crime against others” (90).



On Liberty even considers whether the government properly may regulate pubs

where alcohol is served. In this regard, Mill concludes that because such places are

necessarily social and because public harms associated with drunkenness are more

likely to occur in or near such establishments (at least relative to other public places),

the government may regulate them, setting closing times and restricting operating

licenses to “persons of known or vouched-for respectability” (94). Any other restric-

tions, however, including setting a limit on how many pubs may exist in any given

area, would be overreaching. Such a limit “for the express purpose of rendering them

more difficult of access, and diminishing the occasions of temptation, not only

exposes all to an inconvenience . . . but is suited only to a state of society in which the

labouring classes are avowedly treated as children or savages” (94).

On Liberty stands as a classic document in defense of individual freedom, as rel-

evant and persuasive today as it was in 1859. All elected officials, jurists, and public-




T

HE

I



NDEPENDENT

R

EVIEW



258

R



I C H A R D

G

L E N



B

O I R E


policy makers should read On Liberty, along with the Bill of Rights. Whereas modern-

day politicians, entranced by the “war on drugs,” rapaciously violate “the inward

domain of consciousness” (13) by imposing ever more drug prohibitions and placing

hundreds of thousands of citizens behind bars for drug offenses, On Liberty power-

fully avows that a government grossly exceeds its legitimate power when it interferes

with matters of the mind and the interior condition of its citizenry.



References

Inglis, Brian. 1975. The Forbidden Game: A Social History of Drugs. New York: Charles Scrib-

ner’s Sons.

Mill, John Stuart. 



͓1859͔ 1975. On Liberty. Edited by David Spitz. Toronto: W. W. Norton.

Yüklə 0,56 Mb.

Dostları ilə paylaş:




Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©genderi.org 2024
rəhbərliyinə müraciət

    Ana səhifə