British Journal of Aesthetics Vol 49



Yüklə 139,1 Kb.
Pdf görüntüsü
səhifə7/9
tarix15.08.2018
ölçüsü139,1 Kb.
#62535
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9

COMICS AS LITERATURE? |  231 

  There are problems and unclarities with Goodman’s initial gloss of the distinction. 

47

   More-


over, Goodman’s subsequent account of the autographic/allographic distinction in terms 

of whether or not a work of art is  ‘ amenable to notation ’  is problematic. 

48

   As  Jerrold 



Levinson argues, it is plausible that no actual works of art are such that the identity condi-

tions for genuine instances are completely specifi able in terms of a notation. 

49

   Neverthe-



less, I believe that Goodman was pointing towards a number of important and related 

distinctions that we fi nd in our appreciative practices. Most signifi cantly for the purposes 

of this discussion, there is the intuitive distinction between works of art that do and do not 

seem to allow for a certain kind of forgery — forgery that involves the deceptive practice of 

producing inauthentic items indiscernible from authentic instances of such works. 

 If you accept this distinction, then it is clear that there is an important difference between 

standard comics and standard works of literature. Comics — at least those that are standardly 

produced — are autographic, and they would have been characterized as such by Goodman. 

50

  

The production of an authentic instance of a comic requires mechanical reproduction from a 



template or, perhaps, another authentic instance. 

51

  It is in virtue of this that traditionally made 



comics are intuitively forgeable in the way described above — something may be falsely pre-

sented as if it were mechanically produced in the right way. Moreover, comics are typically 

 completely  autographic; that is, they contain no aesthetically relevant spatial parts that are al-

lographic. 

52

  In particular, it is not the case that typical comics combine autographic images 



with allographic text. The lettering in comics is aesthetically signifi cant and the physically 

embodied text in a comic functions more than merely linguistically. In most cases, the words 

as they appear on page must then be produced by means of the relevant template or they are 

not genuine. Relettering a comic by hand produces something that does not count as a genu-

ine instance of the original. 

53

  The same seems true of the other features of the standard com-



ic book page: panel borders and speech balloons also appear to be autographic elements. 

 Occasionally comics contain bits of typeset text. In some cases (e.g. in Posy Simmonds’s 

recent graphic novel  Tamara Drewe ) these are plausibly allographic elements of the work. 

But I have not been denying that comics may contain some allographic elements. The key 

points here are that being autographic is standard for the category of comics, and that being 

  47    


      For  a  sympathetic  but  critical  discussionm  see  Jerrold  Levinson,   ‘ Autographic  and  Allographic  Art  Revisited’,  in 

 Music, Art, and Metaphysics: Essays in Philosophical Aesthetics  (Ithaca, NY and London: Cornell U.P., 1990), pp. 89 – 107.  

  48            ‘ Since an art seems to be allographic just insofar as it is amenable to notation ’  (Goodman,  Languages of Art , p. 121.)  

  49    


      Levinson,   ‘ Autographic  and  Allographic’,  pp.  100 – 101.  

  50           David Carrier agrees:  ‘ Comics are an autographic art with, potentially, an indefi nite number of copies of the original 

image ’   ( Aesthetics of Comics , p. 63).  

  51           In the case of many traditionally produced comics the particular template is a printing plate. Some comics are 

produced by photocopying. In such cases, the original drawn and inked art may function as the template.  

  52           I assume here that it makes sense to talk of comics having spatial parts. I do not believe that this is an especially 

problematic assumption. Since it is untendentious that the tokens of comics have spatial parts, my claim about the lack 

of allographic spatial parts in comics could be easily translated into talk about the parts of comics that correspond to 

the spatial parts of their tokens.  

  53           And so, letterers count as among the artists who make a comic. This is refl ected in the credits that appear in standard 

commercial comics. And this is true even though the letterers of mainstream comics nowadays commonly use 

graphics software such as Adobe Illustrator.  

 at University of Athens on June 19, 2011

bjaesthetics.oxfordjournals.org

Downloaded from 



 232  | AARON MESKIN

fully or completely autographic is at least typical of comics. Perhaps this latter feature is 

even standard or criterial (although not necessary) for the category. 

 It would be too quick to distinguish comics from literature by combining this result with 

Goodman’s claim that literature is allographic. 

54

  The claim that literature is allographic is an 



overgeneralization. Most essentially illustrated literary works  do  require mechanical repro-

duction from a template for the production of authentic copies and are, in virtue of this, 

forgeable in the relevant sense. Still, these autographic works of literature such as Safran 

Foer’s aforementioned  Extremely Loud and Incredibly Close  and Sterne’s  Tristram Shandy   are 

(except perhaps for some very rare cases — see below) best understood as merely  partially  

autographic. That is, one can cleanly and clearly distinguish their forgeable autographic parts 

from their non-forgeable allographic parts. A specifi c template is only required to produce 

 part or parts  (i.e. distinct spatial parts) of the authentic copy of  Tristram Shandy . Cases which 

suggest the possibility (perhaps actuality) of fully autographic works of literature (e.g.  A Picto-

rial Guide to the Lakeland Fells  by Alfred Wainwright, Spike Milligan’s children’s book,  Badjelly 

the Witch , and Nick Bantock’s hand-illustrated and hand-lettered epistolary Griffi n and Sabine 

novels) are extremely rare. Being fully autographic is contra-standard for being literature. 

 Most comics, then, are fully autographic but being fully autographic provides evidence 

that something is  not  a work of literature. Combine this with the earlier observations about 

the relation between images and words in the two art forms and it looks as if the  ‘ comics 

as literature ’  thesis is under threat. Perhaps there are exceptional comics that are not fully 

autographic and in which there is a preponderance of text over image. But if these were the 

only comics that counted as literature, then the  ‘ comics as literature ’  thesis would be rather 

uninteresting. Of course it is still  possible  that a work may count as literature even if it is 

fully autographic and contains a preponderance of image over text since we are dealing 

with defeasible evidence not entailment. But these are not the only signifi cant differences 

between standard comics and standard works of literature. As we discover more standard 

features of comics that are contra-standard for literature, the evidence that typical comics 

are not literature appears to become overwhelming. 

 Layout is important to ordinary comic books to a degree that is not the case with ordi-

nary works of literature. Many artistic effects produced by comic books are generated by 

particular page layouts. Change the page layout of a comic book and you may signifi cantly 

change the aesthetic and artistic properties of it. But this is not typically the case with 

works of literature — especially non-poetic literature. You may change the layout of a stan-

dard novel, short story, or work of dramatic literature without having any aesthetic or ar-

tistic effect on it whatsoever. Even in the case of poems — where line length is often 

aesthetically signifi cant — larger-scale features of layout are often artistically insignifi cant. 

So, for example, page breaks do not usually play a signifi cant role in poetry even if line 

breaks do. 

55

  Moreover, the fact that most poems can fl ourish purely orally, and hence are 



  54    

      Goodman,   Languages of Art , p. 114.  

  55           I believe that this is true with respect to most poetry. I have on my desk three books that contain Phillip Larkin’s 

poem  ‘ The Whitsun Weddings ’  — each one presents the poem in a different layout. But I cannot say that my 

appreciation of the poem is affected by this. On the other hand, it is true that layout matters very much to concrete 

poetry. See below for further discussion  

 at University of Athens on June 19, 2011

bjaesthetics.oxfordjournals.org

Downloaded from 



Yüklə 139,1 Kb.

Dostları ilə paylaş:
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9




Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©genderi.org 2024
rəhbərliyinə müraciət

    Ana səhifə