Boas and margaret mead as an agenda for revolutionary politics



Yüklə 76,49 Kb.
Pdf görüntüsü
tarix18.07.2018
ölçüsü76,49 Kb.
#56491


35

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

NATURE/NURTURE AND THE ANTHROPOLOGY OF FRANZ

BOAS AND MARGARET MEAD AS AN AGENDA FOR

REVOLUTIONARY POLITICS

1

Sidney M. Greenfield



University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee – Estados Unidos

Abstract: There is much more involved in the nature/nurture debate than an

abstract theoretical disagreement among dispassionate scientists. Each side of the

debate leads logically to significantly different views of the social order and holds

different implications for social policy. In this paper I shall argue that Boas’

Anthropology with its emphasis  on cultural relativism was as much a social and

political agenda as it was a scientific theory. The positions on public policy issues

he opposed were informed (and rationalized) by what its advocates claimed to be

science. To be able to counter the discriminatory policy proposals that followed

from this science, it was necessary for Boas both to challenge its validity and then

replace it with an alternative that would support a more liberal political agenda.

This chapter of anthropology’s history gains relevance in today’s context as

neoevolutionary, reductionist theories once more provide “scientific” support for

conservative, separatist and often discriminatory social policies.

Keywords:  cultural relativism, Franz Boas, History of Anthropology, racial

prejudice.

1

 The inspiration to write this paper emerged while I was planning a conference commemorating the



centenary of Margaret Mead with Professor Morton Klass. We intended to examine the “scientific”

claims of sociobiology, evolutionary psychology and other forms of NeoDarwinian reductionism that

attribute human behavior exclusively to genetic factors and to explore their implications for public

policy. Due to Dr. Klass’ sudden death in April 2001, the conference was put on hold.

Morton Klass and I were fellow students at Columbia University in the mid-1950s, more than a decade

after the death of Franz Boas. At the time Boas’ legacy already was under attack by those wishing

to make the discipline more scientific. We both did study with Margaret Mead among others

influenced by Boas.

This paper is dedicated to my friend and colleague Morton Klass who both professionally and

personally embodied the values attributed in the paper to Boas, Mead and others at Columbia

University and also helped make anthropology more scientific by clarifying the concept of culture

through doing the kind of ethnographic fieldwork its understanding requires.




36

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield



Resumo: O debate natureza/cultura é muito mais do que um desentendimento

teórico e abstrato entre cientistas desapaixonados. Cada lado do debate leva a

visões diferentes da ordem social e traz implicações diferentes para políticas so-

ciais. Neste artigo, sugiro que a Antropologia de Boas, com sua ênfase no

relativismo cultural, tanto quanto uma teoria científica, foi um programa social e

político. As posturas de política pública às quais ele se opunha eram informadas

(e racionalizadas) por algo apresentado por seus proponentes como ciência. Para

combater as propostas discriminatórias que decorriam desta ciência, cabia a Boas

desafiar sua validade  e substituí-la por uma alternativa que daria apoio a uma

agenda política mais liberal.  Esse capítulo da história da antropologia assume

maior relevância no contexto atual em que teorias néo-evolucionistas e

reducionistas mais uma vez fornecem uma base “científica” para políticas sociais

conservadoras, separatistas e freqüentemente discriminatórias.

Palavras-chave:  Franz Boas, história da antropologia, preconceito racial,

relativismo cultural.

As history shows, when translated into the political arena, scientific-

sounding arguments often serve as rationalizations for doing harm to

the most vulnerable elements of society.

Nora Ellen Groce and Jonathan Marks (2000, p. 821)

The discovery that the past might have gone another way is

simultaneously the discovery that the future can be different.

James Carroll (2001, p. 63)

In  The Culture of Critique: An Evolutionary Analysis of Jewish

Involvement in Twentieth-Century Intellectual and Political

Movements, Kevin MacDonald, building on recent attacks on Jewish-

American intellectuals and their scholarly contributions, claims that the

anthropological enterprise developed by Franz Boas and his students at

Columbia University in the early years of the twentieth century was more

of an ethno-political agenda than science (1998, chapter 2). Rather than

counter MacDonald’s baseless ethnic slurs, in this paper I shall accept his




37

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

contention that Boas’ anthropology was as much a social and political agen-

da as it was a scientific theory. The positions on public policy issues he

opposed were informed (and rationalized) by what its advocates claimed to

be science. To be able to counter the discriminatory policy proposals that

followed from this science, it was necessary for Boas both to challenge its

validity and then replace it with an alternative that would support a more

liberal political agenda.

Boas did not invent the idea of fashioning scientific theory for the

purpose of advancing social and political goals. The practice has been part

of Western cultural tradition since the Enlightenment. By the twentieth

century it was so commonplace that most scholars, especially those who

favored the political and economic status quo, had ceased to make explicit

the relationship between their scientific undertakings and proposals for

public policy. They chose instead to maintain, and perhaps even mistakenly

believe, that they were doing some kind of value free, or “pure science”.

This enabled them to charge those, such as Boas, who opposed the policies

their undertakings endorsed, with using science to advance a socio-political

agenda.


Boas and his followers openly opposed discrimination and prejudice

and, since these practices were rationalized and justified by theories that

rested on an evolutionary metaphor, they mounted a systematic attack

against all forms of evolutionary thinking. The need for an alternative

theory to replace evolutionism resulted in the formulation of cultural

relativism with its emphasis on culture as learned and changeable. The

political backlash against public policies and programs put into place based

on this thinking in the post World War II era, combined with new directions

taken within the discipline, explains the vitriolic present day attacks on

Boas and his anthropology by those, such as MacDonald, who oppose the

policies he advocated. It is interesting to note that many of these present day

policies, that resemble those prevailing in the nineteenth and early twentieth

centuries, base their claims on what are reformulated evolutionary, racial

theories. Acknowledging that the science on all sides of public issues may

be used to justify positions on social policies will enable us to see the

debate in a fresh light.

The European nations that adopted Enlightenment thinking, and the

scientific revolution of which it is a product, first encountered substantial




38

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield

numbers of peoples and cultures different from themselves after the

discoveries and expansion of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries

2

 when


they divided up the world to make it into their colonies and later incorporated

specific parts of it into their respective colonial empires. The diverse peoples

had to be dealt with administratively although they were in far away places

and did not have to be encountered and interacted with on a daily basis by

either ordinary citizens or policy makers. The only Europeans who had to be

concerned with the multiplicity of others were the merchants who traded

with them, members of the military who conquered and then policed them,

civil servants who ruled them and the officials and intellectuals who helped

shape and implement the policies that became the laws that governed them.

During the centuries following the discoveries, large amounts of

information describing the peoples of the world physically and reporting on

their behaviors, especially behaviors that differed significantly from those

of the Christian elites of Western Europe who thought and wrote about

them, were being sent back home and accumulating. The question this

growing body of knowledge raised for the intellectual community was how

to account for and explain the great range of diversity in both physical form

and behavior found among the peoples of the world

3

. The answer, as it was



to be when Thomas Kuhn (1970, p. 3-4) later formalized the question as the

starting point for science

4

, was in metaphor. That is, the world of diverse



humanity would be likened to something familiar (and understood by

thinking Europeans) that would make comprehensible that which was

complex and confusing because it was unknown.

By the time of the Enlightenment, after scientific thought had been

separated from religion, the dominant imagery applied in thinking about the

peoples of the world and their diverse behaviors was that of an upwardly

2

 This statement must be modified to acknowledge the role of Jews as the ever-present “other” in the



Christian religious tradition that grew out of the rubble of the disintegration of the Roman Empire to

dominate European belief and thinking up to the present (Carroll, 2001). Although the earliest

Christians were similar to the Jews biologically, the Europeans to adopt the faith later – who were

different – used the physical features that differentiated the groups as distinguishing negative makers.

The Africans, Asians and peoples of the Western Hemisphere discovered during the expansion differed

even more in terms of their looks and behaviors.

3

 The explanations, of course, would have to support the continuing dominance of the others by the



governments of the nations of Europe.

4

 What must the world be like for man to know it? (Kuhn, 1970).




39

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

slopping line, or a ladder, with each group, or their characteristics, placed

hierarchically on rungs in descending order down from Europeans who were

placed solidly at the top. This imagery, as Robert Nisbet (1969) noted, was

derived from Greek thinking that likened human society to a living organism

whose growth, from birth to death, was used to explain the behavior of

social groups. For the Greeks, and the Romans to follow them, each of the

many peoples in the world was assumed to have its own distinctive growth

cycle. The Church fathers substituted the idea of a single humanity whose

growth manifested itself in a series of epochs or stages. Secular thinkers

adopted this imagery of developmental stages as their means of organizing

the large amount of data accumulating on human populations. In some

scenarios proposed, total societies were placed in an ascending sequence on

the ladder that was believed to demonstrate the evolution of human society.

In others, isolated pieces of information, describing some aspect of the

religious, political, or other behavior of a particular group were taken out

of their lived context and placed in one or another of the categories of what

was presented as a universalistic developmental sequence (of religion,

family, etc.) offered as another view of the evolution of humanity. Since the

standard for which behaviors were to be considered most advanced were

those of the intellectuals who were the authors of the schemas, the data that

differed most from their own beliefs and practices were taken to represent

the earliest or most primitive stages of human life. The remaining categories

were placed in ascending order to represent more advanced or developed

stages according to how closely each approximated the social practices of

the writer.

The imagery of hierarchically arranged stages of development, that

came to be know as the theory of cultural evolution, took an unanticipated

twist when it was placed within the Linnaean scheme of biological

classification. Previously, the focus in ordering the data on human diversity

was primarily the behaviors of peoples in their social groups with the

physical characteristics of the actors being secondary

5

. Now the physical



characteristics of the races, the subcategories of the single species into

which all humanity was placed, were equated with behaviors. Consequently,

5

 The Linnaean system was intended to classify all forms of life. It had unanticipated consequences



when applied in terms of the framework of the metaphor of developmental stages to human

populations.




40

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield

race and social and cultural behavior came to be fused and seen as

interdependent. The assumption, which is still an unsubstantiated premise in

racist arguments, was that the former, the biological, was the cause of the

latter, or cultural.

The racial categories, in what came to be a variant of evolutionary

thinking, were placed on the steps of the ladder, again starting with the

Western Europeans – now as a race, or series of sub-races – at the top with

the others in descending order down to those races most different from

them. Those at the lower end were assumed to be less advanced biologically

and behaviorally than those above them and especially those at the top.

Without then examining the relationship between the biological and

the social, the evolutionists assumed, as their intellectual descendants still

do today, the ontological priority of what later became the nature/nurture

oppositional debate. This enabled them to focus on what for them were

more pressing (political) questions.

As long as the others were in distant places the practical consequences

of this had no immediate impact on the peoples of the nations to which the

writers belonged. Except for colonial administrators, merchants and

soldiers, the policy implications of evolutionary theory and its racist variant

did not impact on the daily lives of the peoples of Western Europe. This,

of course, was not the case in the United States, or in Western Europe today

after the post World War II immigration of large numbers of former colonial

populations.

Unlike the polities of Western Europe, the United States first came into

being as a colony. The earliest wave of primarily Anglo-Saxon settlers

succeeded in pushing the native peoples they encountered far enough into

the western interior so that by the time it won its independence most of

these “others” were sufficiently far away so that they did not have to be

dealt with on a daily basis. Interestingly, these indigenous peoples were

called “savages” by the Europeans, a name used for one of the earlier stages

in most schemes of human evolution. The peoples from Africa, brought as

slaves, who generally were assigned to the least evolved category,

represented a special situation to which I shall return shortly.

This demographic situation was to change irrevocably when following

its industrialization in the early to mid-nineteenth century the United States

began receiving large numbers of immigrants. Between 1880 and 1920 some




41

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

tens of millions of people, mostly from Central, Southern and Eastern

Europe, who differed both in their physical appearances as well as in their

linguistic, religious and other social behaviors from the Anglo-Saxons,

entered the country. How these differences were to be explained would

determine the way they would be treated and incorporated into the body

politic.


The first example of diversity Americans had coped with – aside from

the native peoples who had been removed physically, or at times massacred

– were the Africans who had been brought during the colonial period to

work the plantations of the south. According to the racial variants of

evolutionary theory then prevalent in Europe, which were accepted and used

to justify bondage in the United States, Africans were at the bottom of the

evolutionary scale, peoples whose innate abilities were believed to be so

minimal that they were placed even below the indigenous people. Their

descendants were to remain, to paraphrase Carroll (2001, p. 16), the

extreme negative of humanity in (American) popular mythology.

Since so many of the slave masters were among the political elites who

participated in the writing of the American constitution and in framing the

laws of the land that set out what were to be acceptable codes of conduct

governing social relations, the legal system of the United States had built

into it a special status for Africans and their descendants that limited their

participation in the institutions of national life. These slave codes, followed

by the regulations supporting segregation and Jim Crow after emancipation,

constituted an extreme model for the treatment of some post-Civil War

immigrants. In the United States, then, racist evolutionary theories already

were in place as an explanation for diversity. It is not surprising that they

were used in public debates on the policies that would affect the extent to

which the new arrivals would be able to participate in national economic,

political and social life. The future of these immigrants might have

depended on where they, as members of groups or categories, would be

placed on the imaginary ladder. Furthermore, the extent to which any

specific group could be shown to approximate Africans, Indians, or others

near the bottom of the ladder who were assumed to be biologically and

mentally inferior (Stocking, 1968), would greatly limit the opportunities that

would be available to them; and, in the extreme, this would lead to

proposals ranging from eugenics to the closing off of immigration.




42

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield

Franz Boas came to the United States at the beginning of the large-

scale immigration in the late 1880s. He was one of the many newcomers

whose future would be influenced by public debates over the abilities and

potentials (or lack thereof) of the various groups of newcomers. By his late

twenties he already had earned a Ph.D. in his native Germany and had

served his compulsory year in its military. He chose an academic career and

a life in the United States. “What I want to live and die for,” he wrote “is

equal rights for all, equal possibilities to learn and work for poor and rich

alike!” (Cole, 1983, p. 37).

Born in 1858 into a family that strongly espoused the principles of the

unsuccessful revolution of 1848, Boas, like many German Jews of the

period, passionately embraced its beliefs that included the value of science,

its application to acquire knowledge that would improve the human

condition and freedom for the individual to better himself while

contributing to advancing society and the world around him

6

.



Among the members of this politically liberal, intellectually self-

conscious group that influenced Boas in his formative years was Rudolph

Virchow, “a physician, pathologist, scientist and radical activist, who was

prominent in German science and politics” (Lewis, in press). Boas admired

and emulated Virchow (Stocking, 1974, p. 22) and took a course in

anthropometry with him before embarking on a field trip to Baffin Island.

After participating in daily life there, Boas developed great respect for the

Inuit people and for their customs. He realized how little was actually

known about them, or many other small-scale, marginal (then called

primitive) groups like them, other than the implications to be deduced from

the place assigned them in the varying evolutionary schemas. What he was

to learn about the Inuit, and other people he was to study as his career

unfolded, led him to question the accuracy of the rigid system on which

evolutionary thinking was based. As a result, he systematically opposed all

forms of classifying peoples into categories, insisting instead on the

importance of individuality. Given the social and political implications of

evolutionary theories for the American society to which he committed

himself, Boas first task was to challenge their scientific accuracy, which he

6

 Their heroes, as Lewis (in press) notes, included Kant, Herder, Goethe, Schiller, Lessing, Moses



Mendelssohn, Beethoven and the Von Humbolt brothers.


43

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

would do both theoretically and with ethnographic data similar to what he

collected on Baffin Island. More importantly, he would re-conceptualize

anthropology, which was dominated at the time by evolutionary thinking

(Harris, 1968), transforming it into the science that, in his view, would

improve conditions by advancing his humanistic and individualistic beliefs.

Boas began his re-formulation of anthropology by taking the

evolutionary metaphor and turning it over on its side. The result was a view

of humanity in which each group, or culture, the term he used to refer to the

total way of life of each population, became in a sense like the individuals

Boas so greatly admired, each unique and distinctive with its own practices,

values and worth. In terms of this new framework, Western Europeans and

their former North American colonials no longer would represent the

pinnacle and standard by which others were to be judged. Each culture

instead was to be seen as the product of its own unique history that resulted

in a set of beliefs, values and behaviors that were to be accepted on par, but

different from, those of Western Europe and North America and each other.

The implications of this imagery came to be known as cultural relativism.

The behavior of each individual, always foremost in Boas’ thinking,

was to be understood and judged exclusively in terms of the standards

prevailing in the culture into which he had been born and raised. More

importantly, Boas and his followers proceeded with the assumption that

human behavior was learned rather than the inevitable consequences of

biology, climate or any other factors. Furthermore, Boas was to take the lead

in promoting the importance of ethnographic studies – that would lead to

the systematic collection of data on the lives and cultures of peoples here-

to-fore unstudied directly by scholars. This cornerstone of the

anthropological science he was building was to be no greater in his overall

concerns than the effort he would devote to helping build the scientifically

based, rational culture that he hoped would emerge in the United States.

Boas view of humanity, as an array of diverse and morally equivalent

groups of peoples and their cultures, was to provide the imagery out from

which multiculturalism and identity politics was to develop in the last

several decades of the twentieth century. Ironically, advocates of these

highly politicized positions have vilified Boas, to the point of even

questioning the sincerity of his efforts to counter racism (Visenwaran, 1998;

Willis, 1969).




44

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield

Boas was not a multiculturalist, nor is it likely that he would have looked

favorably on movements of identity politics. As we have seen, he recognized,

respected and helped describe many of the mostly small-scale, local cultures

with which peoples now identify, but he viewed them as anachronisms, to be

documented and then discarded rather than revered. Although he believed

that there were things of value in all cultures that might be incorporated into

the rational composite of the future, most customs from the past, of his own

and other societies, were to him more the “shackles of dogma” (Stocking,

1974, p. 41-42), “the irrational authority of tradition” (Stocking, 1979, p. 96)

than something to be accepted uncritically and perpetuated. Boas wished to

replace custom with new forms according to which it would be possible to

attain the universal rational knowledge that would be the basis for the culture

of the future. In his view each of us, as individuals, should be provided the

freedom to contribute to and participate in the new way of life being

developed. In this sense Boas was an assimilationist and an integrationist.

He wanted everyone to participate fully and equally in the new world under

construction.

This perspective is the very antithesis of multiculturalism and identity

politics. It also strongly opposed the view of American – and world –

society that followed from the racist, eugenicist and other evolutionary

views advocated by his adversaries in his era.

Much of Boas’ own research – other than his ethnographic studies –

focused on testing, with the intent of disproving, the usually unsubstantiated

assertions of racist thinkers. Basic to these undertakings was his conviction

that human behavior, for the most part, was learned rather than inherent in

our biology. This aspect of Boas’ program, that was to be a central feature

of his anthropological legacy, was made explicit in the work of his students,

specifically Margaret Mead.

Mead first met Boas when she was an undergraduate at Barnard

College. She pursued graduate studies under his direction at Columbia

University because, as she wrote in 1949, he “and Ruth Benedict had

presented the tasks of anthropology as more urgent than any other task

which lay ready to the choice of a student of human behavior.” When she

went to Samoa

7

, in 1924 at the age of 23, she acknowledged her debt to



7

 Samoa at the time only recently had become a US possession that had been brought to public

attention in the press and in a film by ethnographic filmmaker Robert Flaherty.



45

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

Boas, not only for her training, but also for inspiring and directing her in

framing her research problem. The questions she asked were: “Are the

disturbances which vex our adolescents due to the nature of adolescence

itself or to the civilization? Under different conditions does adolescence

present a different picture?” (Mead, 1928) Underlying these questions, and

her research, was the much larger issue that was central to the theoretical

framework being developed by Boas: To what extent does human behavior

derive from biological heritage as against social (cultural) environment?



Coming of Age in Samoa (1928), published shortly after Mead

defended her doctoral dissertation, caused a sensation. At one level the book

presented a fascinating account of female adolescence in American Samoa;

but, at another, it was both a critique of prevailing theories of adolescence

advanced by scholars and accepted by professionals and a framework for

rethinking the theories and changing practices.

The argument was simple but with devastating implications.

Adolescence in the United States, at the time of the study, was believed to

be a period of stress and strain. Public opinion was focused on the subject

because of the publicity given the activities of some young women during

the “roaring twenties.” If Mead could show that this was not the case in

Samoa, it would prove that the difficulties were not  inherent in any

inevitable human nature, but were instead the result of the particular forms

of child rearing to which American adolescents were exposed. If this were

the case, we could change our child rearing practices to mitigate and

perhaps even eliminate the difficulties of adolescence, especially as

experienced by females.

Several implications of the study for the future of anthropology and its

place both in the social sciences and in public thinking and policy

formulation must be made explicit. First, what Mead accomplished was to

establish in both public understanding and in scientific thought, was that

other cultures could be used as a database against which general statements

about assumed universal human characteristics and behaviors made

exclusively on the basis of observations in the West could be tested. That

is, if generalizations made by theoreticians about adolescent girls in the

name of science could be shown not to occur in Samoa – or any other

culture – this would disprove (falsify) the proposition that it was rooted in

our (biological) humanity. Second, if Samoan adolescents behaved




46

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield

differently from their North American counterparts it could only be because

the behavior (of adolescence) was learned and Samoans had been exposed

to different experiences than Americans. If this were so, it followed that

adolescent behavior could be changed by modifying the circumstances to

which children were exposed.

Here was the truly revolutionary social and political potential of Boas’

anthropological paradigm. Human beings were in control of their own

behavior. If they did not like something in their culture, they could change it.



The Coming of Age in Samoa, according the Mead, was not written as

a “popular” book. It also was not a technical monograph intended for an

audience of professional anthropologists or other scholars. Instead, it was a

book written in simple and straightforward language “that would be

communicative to those who had the most to do with adolescents – teachers,

parents and soon-to-be parents,” asking them to rethink what they were

doing in the light of her report. This idea of transforming behaviors

considered to be unwanted or undesirable by modifying other behavior was

tremendously empowering. It gave people the ability to transform their lives

and their futures.

If Boas, Mead, and an anthropology based the concept of culture as

learned behavior that differed from group to group and place to place and

was susceptible to being changed were right, people no longer were bound

to accept as inevitable social forms received from previous generations.

They could change them by changing themselves and what they did. They

no longer needed leaders or reformers. They, themselves, could provide the

direction.

This was the kind of scientific thinking with which it would be

possible to build a more rational, liberal and democratic world.

Furthermore, instead of assuming that the traditions of the West, its

economic practices, family and kinship patterns, religions and rituals, etc.,

were the inevitable end point of human evolution and debating who would

be permitted to participate in them and to what degree, a new culture could

be developed by combining selections from among what was known (and

invented) in the West with practices from the range of other cultures being

studied. The ethnographic record, as being assembled from the

investigations of specific cultures by anthropologists, could be gleaned to

find out what in human experience worked and what should be avoided




47

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

(Boas, 1928; Kluckhohn, 1957). If culture was learned rather than innate,

and based on one’s membership in a group or category, all peoples, no

matter their place of birth or upbringing, could participate fully and equally

as individuals by learning the new practices. It was never that human

behavior could be explained as something determined solely by culture.

Rather, before one dare conclude that some specific human activity is uni-

versal, based on an untested assumption or studies conducted only in

European societies – not to speak of slime molds or laboratory animals as

is being done by the present generation of evolutionist scientists – it was

necessary to compile data on variations in different cultural settings: only

thus could one hope to clarify what was a result of cultural conditioning and

what was biology.

America’s entry into World War II drastically changed the focus of

national concern and with it the framework of political debate. To mobilize

for the war effort it was necessary to unify the population that here-to-fore

had been kept apart by the separatist ideology that dominated public debate.

The integrationist premises of the anthropological science of Boas, Mead

and others were more supportive of the need to bring together all members

of the national society behind the war effort than its predecessor and

alternative. As Karen Brodkin put it in her discussion of the sudden

American acceptance of the descendants of European immigrants, “The war

against fascism led to a more inclusive version of whiteness.” “Instead of

dirty and dangerous races that would destroy American democracy,

immigrants became ethnic groups whose children had successfully

assimilated into the mainstream…” (Brodkin, 1998, p. 36). Under the

guidance of this new liberal philosophy that supported the incorporation of its

“white” citizens as individuals, America succeeded not only in winning the

war, but also in emerging from it as the most powerful nation in the world.

In the post war period the American economy grew rapidly and its

society was transformed. With the help of the GI Bill, the sons of once

disparaged immigrants went to college and earned degrees that qualified

them for jobs in the rapidly growing industries that eventually would

become multinational. Aided by FHA and VA mortgages they bought homes

in the suburbs where they and their children achieved a degree of

assimilation that the earlier political policies based on the separatist

philosophy had denied to their parents.




48

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield

Programs to rebuild the economies and societies of our allies, and of

our European and Japanese adversaries, and beginning a decade later to help

develop and “modernize” the new nations emerging from a discredited

colonialism, also were guided by the new liberal philosophy that was based

on the premise that human behavior and the institutions of society were

learned and not rooted in a nature. In the period from the onset of World

War II through perhaps the end of the Vietnam War and the height of the

Civil Rights movement, a liberal political imagery, based in considerable

part on the anthropological view of the world, dominated public thinking in

America. It was central in debate and formulation of public policy. Mead

became an American icon. Anthropology was accepted as one of the basic

social sciences and programs and departments proliferated as part of the

rapid growth of universities. The growing number of professional

anthropologists, assuming the battle over racism and social acceptance of all

citizens had been won, turned their attention away from public debates and

social policy issues and devoted their efforts to elaborating the scholarly

and academic aspects of the disciplinary agenda.

As the twenty-first century opens, this view of the world many

anthropologists came to take for granted is being challenged, within the

academy by proponents in fields with names such as sociobiology,

evolutionary psychology and molecular biology, and, perhaps more

importantly, in civic discourse. Those advocating these new reductionist

theories, which are based on the same evolutionary imagery that informed

last century’s separatist, discriminatory political agendas, point to

anthropology as the basis for what people otherwise as diverse in their

academic backgrounds and areas of specialization as Edward O. Wilson

(1999, p. 200-201) and Steven Pinker (1994, p. 404-412) call the “Standard

Social Science Model”. They erroneously claim that anthropology attributes

the full explanation for all human behavior to learning, culture, or what they

oversimplify as environment

8

.

The authors of the many books and papers advocating the new



evolutionary reductionisms are neither racists nor eugenicists, but their as

8

 These scholars do not use the word culture, nor do they acknowledge and make reference to the



database of cross-cultural materials collected by anthropologists that would falsify many of their

claims. In fact, they appear to be referring more to the behaviorism of B. F. Skinner and his

followers in psychology than to the thinking and research results of anthropology.



49

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

yet unsubstantiated claims that human behavior is to be explained exclusively

by means of our genes

9

, support conservative views of social reality that



rationalize the status quo (with all of its institutionalized racism and other

discriminatory practices) and promote it as inevitable. If our genes alone

account for our behavior, it follows that there is nothing much we can do

about it other than to acknowledge the social consequences of the world in

which we find ourselves and then learn to live with it

10

.



Nelkin and Lindee (1995, p. 100) summarize the implications of the new

reductionism for civic discourse and social policy making in words that

echo the Calvinist idea of for-ordination. They write:

The appropriation of DNA – the good or bad gene – to explain indi-

vidual differences recasts common beliefs about the importance of

heredity in powerful scientific terms. Science becomes a way to

empower prevailing beliefs, justifying existing social categories and

expectations as based on natural forces. The great, the famous, the

rich and successful, are what they are because of their genes. So too,

the deviant and the dysfunctional are genetically fated. Opportunity is

less important than predisposition. Some are destined for success,

others for problems or, at least, a lesser fate.

If our genes do determine our fate, why should society’s resources be

expended to educate new immigrants and other minorities doomed to

failure? If  “criminal” behavior is programmed in their genes, why make the

effort to rehabilitate young, black, male offenders? Or, for that matter, why

even think about public policy as a means to improve the human condition?

There is much more involved in the nature/nurture debate than an

abstract theoretical disagreement among dispassionate scientists. Each side of

what continues to be framed in terms of an uncompromising opposition – in

9

 This position has been followed by most molecular biologists, evolutionary psychologists and



sociobiologists since Francis Crick’s (1957) first formulated the “dogma” of DNA—>RNA—>

protein, attributing ontological priority exclusively to the genes.

10

 A startling example of this was the recent review in the Sunday New York Times Book Review



Section of Mean Genes by Burnham and Phelan, a book in which the authors, according to the

reviewer, after accepting the argument for the power of genes to explain human behavior, offer

“practical steps for better living” [a self help book to deal with the inevitable consequences

of genetic determinism]. Although the book was dismissed intellectually, the fact that the

editors of the Times chose to review it demonstrates the influence this line of thinking has

in popular literary circles.




50

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield

spite of repeated denials on both sides – leads logically to significantly different

views of the social order. Since neither side is able at present to muster a

sufficient combination of theory and data to convince the other, the debate will

continue well into the future. In the meantime, I suggest that we consider the

public policy implications of both positions, which brings me back to the

criticism that Franz Boas’ anthropology was more of a social and political

agenda than a science. I have argued that in some respects it was; that Boas’

anthropology was formulated as the science to counter the prevailing one that,

among other things, justified social exclusion, discrimination and prejudice.

Today’s neoevolutionary, reductionist theories, whether their proponents intend

it or not, once more provide “scientific” support for conservative, separatist

and often discriminatory social policies.

The more relevant debate is to be found in the realm of politics. In the

absence of conclusive proof, why should concerned citizens opt for a

position that implies that their social world is the product of forces over

which they have no control? Why should they accept that the institutions,

rules and practices to be found in the West are inevitable? Would it not be

wiser for them to choose the position that leads to the belief that they are

the masters of their own destinies? Perhaps it is time for those who believe,

as did Boas, Mead and several generations of anthropologists, that human

beings are able to invent and implement cultural forms other than those

presently found in the West, to raise their voices once more in public de-

bates on social issues where the contest over the discourse that is to inform

public policy is being waged.

Although anthropological thinking, its research activities and

methodological approaches, have been criticized, both appropriately and

not, and have changed in the past half-century, it is now time to reaffirm in

public the basic view of the world the discipline continues to teach: that

human beings are not simply the products of their genes – mean, selfish or

other. With respect to their social, political, economic and other behaviors,

they are able to invent and implement practices different from those that

dominate our present Euro-American world. It is time for anthropologists to

revive their concern with social policy and make it once again central. The

result can be, in the spirit of what Carroll said in the epigraph to this paper

– and Boas and Mead believed – that the future will be different because

we did what was necessary to make the present different.




51

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Nature/Nurture and the Anthropology of Franz Boas...

References

BOAS, Franz. Anthropology and modern life. New York: W. W. Norton & Company,

Inc., 1928.

BRODKIN, Karen. How Jews became white folks and what that says about race



in America. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1998.

CARROLL, James. Constantine’s sword, the Church and the Jews: a history.

Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 2001.

COLE, Douglas. The value of a person lies in his “Herzensbildung”; Franz Boas’

Baffin island letter-diary, 1883-1884. In: STOCKING Jr., George W. (Ed). Observers

observed: essays on ethnographic fieldwork. Madison, Wiscosin: University of

Wisconsin Press, 1983.

FREEMAN, Derek. Margaret Mead and Samoa: the making and unmaking of an

anthropological myth. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1983.

GROCE, Nora Ellen; MARKS, Jonathan. The great apes project and disability rights:

ominous undercurrents of eugenics in action. American Anthropologist, 102, p. 818-

822, 2000.

HARRIS, Marvin. The rise of anthropological theory: a history of theories of

culture. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1968.

KUHN, Thomas S. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of

Chicago Press, 1970.

LEWIS, Herbert S. The passion of Franz Boas. American Anthropologist. In press.

MacDONALD, Kevin. The culture of critique: an evolutionary analysis of Jewish

involvement in twentieth-century intellectual and political movements. Westport:

Praeger, 1998.

MEAD, Margaret. Coming of age in Samoa. New York: William Morrow &

Company, 1928.

NELKIN, Dorothy; LINDEE, M. Susan. The DNA mystique: the gene as cultural icon.

New York: W. H. Freeman and Company, 1995.

NISBET, Robert A. Social change and history. London: Oxford University Press,

1969.

PINKER, Steven. The language instinct: how the mind creates language. New York:



Harper Collins Publishers, 1994.

STOCKING Jr., George W. Race, culture, and evolution: essays in the history of

Anthropology. New York: The Free Press, 1968.



52

Horizontes Antropológicos, Porto Alegre, ano 7, n. 16, p. 35-52, dezembro de 2001

Sidney M. Greenfield

STOCKING Jr., George W. The shaping of American Anthropology, 1883-1911: a

Franz Boas reader. New York: Basic Books, 1974.

______. Anthropology as “Kulturkampf”: science and politics in the Visweswaran,

Kamala “Race and the culture of anthropology”. American Anthropologist, 100, p.

70-83, 1998.

WILLIS Jr., William S. Skeletons in the anthropological closet. In: HYMES, Dell

(Ed.). Reinventing Anthropology. New York: Random House, 1969. p. 121-152.

WILSON, Edward O. Consilience: the unity of knowledge. New York: Vintage



Books, 1999.

Yüklə 76,49 Kb.

Dostları ilə paylaş:




Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©genderi.org 2024
rəhbərliyinə müraciət

    Ana səhifə