Causal Analytics for Applied Risk Analysis Louis Anthony Cox, Jr


Lopiano KK, Smith RL, Young SS. Air quality and acute deaths in California, 2000-2012. https://arxiv.org/abs/1502.03062



Yüklə 12,64 Mb.
səhifə55/57
tarix25.07.2018
ölçüsü12,64 Mb.
#58662
1   ...   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57

Lopiano KK, Smith RL, Young SS. Air quality and acute deaths in California, 2000-2012. https://arxiv.org/abs/1502.03062

Maldonado G. Toward a clearer understanding of causal concepts in epidemiology. Ann Epidemiol. 2013 Dec;23(12):743-9.


Nelson JM, Chiller TM, Powers JH, Angulo FJ. Fluoroquinolone-resistant Campylobacter species and the withdrawal of fluoroquinolones from use in poultry: a public health success story.Clin Infect Dis. 2007 Apr 1;44(7):977-80. 
O'Malley AJ. Instrumental variable specifications and assumptions for longitudinal analysis of mental health cost offsets.HealthServ Outcomes Res Methodol. 2012 Dec;12(4):254-272.
Pearl J. An introduction to causal inference.Int J Biostat. 2010 Feb 26;6(2):Article 7. 
Pearl J. (2009). Causality: Models, Reasoning and Inference 2nd Edition. Cambridge University Press. New York, New York.
Powell MR. Trends in Reported Foodborne Illness in the United States; 1996-2013.Risk Anal. 2016 Aug;36(8):1589-98. 
Pope CA 3rd, Cropper M, Coggins J, Cohen A.Health benefits of air pollution abatement policy: Role of the shape of the concentration-response function.J Air Waste Manag Assoc. 2015 May; 65(5):516-22.
Pope CA, 3rd, Burnett RT, Thun MJ, et al. Lung cancer, cardiopulmonary mortality, and long-term exposure to fine particulate air pollution. JAMA. 2002;287:1132–1141. 
Price LB, Lackey LG, Vailes R, Silbergeld E. The persistence of fluoroquinolone-resistant Campylobacter in poultry production. Environ Health Perspect. 2007 Jul;115(7):1035-9.
Rottman BM, Hastie R. Reasoning about causal relationships: Inferences on causal networks.Psychol Bull. 2014 Jan;140(1):109-39. doi: 10.1037/a0031903.
Schwartz J. Air pollution and daily mortality: a review and meta analysis. Environ Res. 1994;64:36–52.
Schwartz J, Austin E, Bind MA, Zanobetti A, Koutrakis P. Estimating Causal Associations of Fine Particles With Daily Deaths in Boston.Am J Epidemiol. 2015 Oct 1;182(7):644-50. 
Schwartz J, Bind MA, Koutrakis P. Estimating Causal Effects of Local Air Pollution on Daily Deaths: Effect of Low Levels.Environ Health Perspect. 2016 May 20.
Schwartz J, Dockery DW, Neas LM. Is daily mortality associated specifically with fine particles? J Air Waste Manag Assoc. 1996;46:927–939.
Schwartz J, Laden F, Zanobetti A. The concentration-response relation between PM(2.5) and daily deaths.Environ Health Perspect. 2002 Oct;110(10):1025-9.
Simon, H. A. (1953). Causal order and identifiability. In W. C. Hood & T. C. Koopmans (Eds.), Studies in econometric method. Cowles Commission Monograph (pp. 49–74). New York: Wiley
Tetlock PE, Gardner D. (2015) Superforecasting: The Art and Science of Prediction. Penguin Random House LLC. New York, New York.
Wang Y, Kloog I, Coull BA, Kosheleva A, Zanobetti A, Schwartz JD. Estimating Causal Effects of Long-Term PM2.5 Exposure on Mortality in New Jersey.Environ Health Perspect. 2016 Aug;124(8):1182-8
Weick, Karl E.; Kathleen M. Sutcliffe (2001). Managing the Unexpected - Assuring High Performance in an Age of Complexity. San Francisco, CA, USA: Jossey-Bass. pp. 10–17.
Woodward J, "Causation and Manipulability", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = .
Wu MH, Frye RE, Zouridakis G. A comparison of multivariate causality based measures of effective connectivity.ComputBiol Med. 2011 Dec;41(12):1132-41
Wynne B. Public Uptake of Science: A case for institutional reflexivity. Public Understanding of Science. 1993;2(4):321-37.

Chapter 15



Intergenerational Justice in Protective and Resilience Investments with Uncertain Future Preferences and Resources
This final chapter considers the challenging question of how much each generation should invest in building resilient infrastructure to protect against possible future natural disasters. If such disasters are infrequent, members of each generation may be tempted to defer investments in resilience and protective infrastructure (e.g., in building or improving dams and levees; retrofitting office and residential buildings; creating more robust transportation, power, and communications networks; etc.) in favor of consumption or growth. Succumbing to this temptation imposes risks on future generations of needlessly large losses or disproportionate need to invest in resilience. Yet, even the most dutiful and altruistic present generation has limited obligations to invest to protect future ones, especially if present investments in resilience reduce growth and future prosperity, or if the preferences, priorities, resources, and capabilities of future generations are highly uncertain. This chapter presents several different frameworks for clarifying how much each generation should invest in protection, drawing on and extending ideas and methods for collaborative and adaptive decision-making discussed in earlier chapters. It introduces optimal economic growth models, which provide a well-developed technical framework for maximizing average or minimal expected social utility over time, but require consistency and cooperation over time that may not be psychologically or politically realistic. If investment decisions are viewed as a form of dynamic “dictator game” in which earlier generations choose how to allocate benefits between themselves and later generations, then insights from behavioral economics, risk psychology, and moral psychology suggest that cues related to deservingness and trustworthiness powerfully affect what is perceived as fair and right in such settings. We propose that a Rawlsian concept of justice (what investment decision rules would people choose from behind a veil of ignorance, in which no one knew what generation he or she would be born into?) can address problems of over-discounting long-delayed and uncertain consequences that have frustrated some previous efforts to apply cost-benefit analysis to ethically charged issues involving intergenerational justice.

This chapter closes by suggesting several principles for applying insights from these different frameworks to investments in building resilient communities and mitigating natural disaster risks across generations. Principles of prescriptive, collaborative, and learning analytics introduced in Chapter 1 and developed in the last several chapters – adaptive optimization, collaboration among multiple decisionmakers, and learning from experience – are shown to be useful for dynamic optimization of societal risk management decisions across generations, as well as for the individual, group, and organizational decisions.


Introduction: How Much Care Does Each Generation Owe to Future Ones?
Each of us lives with decisions that our former selves have made – choices about what to read and study, whom to marry, where to live, what to work at, how hard to work, how much to consume, and what to do with any savings. Our satisfaction with the choices made by our prior selves may be mixed, but it is not unusual to find that our own current choices are only modestly responsive to the imagined preferences and evaluations of our future selves (Kahneman, 2011). And so we may let slide New Year’s resolutions that our future selves will predictably wish we had abided by; spend more on current consumption and less on savings or prudent investments or retirement plans than our censorious future selves will, predictably, deem optimal; and succumb to tempting but risky prospects in the heat of the present moment knowing that, with high probability, we will soon regret them as imprudent choices that we will (predictably) wish we had made differently.

Researchers investigating individual preferences and choices over time and under uncertainty have long noted, and created analytic models of, the dynamic inconsistency of individual plans and intentions formed under realistic (hyperbolically discounted) preferences for future rewards (ibid). More usefully, they have developed a large array of devices for improving the time-consistency of present decisions to help us make present choices that are less regrettable to our future selves. These devices range from freezing credit cards in block of ice to changing defaults and nudges (e.g., to opt-in or opt-out of an employer-sponsored savings or retirement plans such as Save More Tomorrow) to encouraging “pre-mortem” thinking about how well-intended plans and projects might come to be seen in retrospect as predictable failures. Such imposition of dynamic consistency and rationality constraints and effortful (“System 2”) deliberation to restrain and modify the choices urged by immediate intuitive and impulsive (“System 1”) responses to the opportunities and temptations before us, is at the forefront of current efforts to improve real-world decision-making for individuals by better integrating and coordinating the recommendations from Systems 1 and 2 (Kahneman, 2011). It also corresponds to venerable traditions in personal ethics that extol the virtues of temperance, patience, prudence, thrift, steadfastness, and the like.



Social decision-making, too, raises questions of how best to trade-off the needs and preferences of current vs. future agents. In many cases, these agents include members of present and future generations, rather than only our own selves at earlier and later dates. Crucial practical risk management policies and social investment decisions depend on how we trade-off their interests. For example,

  • How large a tsunami, hurricane, earthquake or other natural disaster should nuclear power plant designers, levee designers, sea wall builders, and other construction and infrastructure engineers design for? Following experiences with extreme events such as the Fukushima tsunami or Hurricane Sandy, it is common for news stories, editorials, and politicians to urge that more should have been done and should be done now to provide for facilities that would better withstand the stresses of wind and water under such extreme conditions. Hindsight bias may make such criticisms and recommendations inevitable. But should engineers henceforth design for the most extreme events that are expected to occur on average once every 50 years, or 100 years, or 1000 years, or for some other level of extremity? Designing to protect against more extreme (rarer) events typically costs more, but the future risk reduction benefits purchased by these present investments in safety may be very uncertain, depending on part on future climate and weather.

  • How much should we invest in developing and stockpiling antibiotics and other countermeasures in case of an anthrax (or other) outbreak? The preventive measures cost money now. Whether they will be used before they expire, and how much good they will do if they are used, are typically quite uncertain. If the decision problem is stationary (i.e., looks the same starting from any point on time), then it may be reduced to a choice between (A) Creating and maintaining some level of stockpiled countermeasures, costing a certain amount per year; or (B) Foregoing the costs and benefits of doing so. In either case, some people alive now and others not yet born may share in the costs, risks, and benefits resulting from whatever decision is made.

  • How much should we spend now in seeking to postpone or mitigate future losses from climate change? Is it better to commit a substantial fraction of present GDP to climate change mitigation efforts, or to invest in current economic growth and technological and institutional progress, that so that future generations will be better equipped to deal with any problems that materialize?

  • How much should we spend per year on nuclear fusion reactor research? If there is substantial uncertainty about whether and when fusion-generated power production might become practical (e.g., at least producing more power than it consumes), then how much should the current generation invest in fusion R&D? Under what conditions (if any) should it stop investing in favor of more promising alternative uses of current resources? If future generations were allowed to vote on or have input to current decisions, how (if at all) would that change the answers?

These examples, and countless others in the realms of public finance and investments, consumption of non-renewable resources, costly exploration and discovery initiatives, storage of radioactive wastes, and even military investments in long-term security and readiness, illustrate the challenges and importance of learning to address preferences and trade-offs in decisions with consequences that affect multiple generations. All of them can be posed generically as decisions about how much care (whether measured in prevention, investment, or other expenditures) current decision-makers should take in order to benefit future recipients of the benefits of these decisions. Making such decisions wisely requires constructive frameworks for determining both what we should decide to do now, and how we should decide what to do now, given that some of those who bear the consequences may not be alive yet to participate in the decisions.

Optimizing trade-offs between present costs of taking care (or investing in risk reduction) and uncertain future risk-reduction benefits requires an approach to decision-making different from traditional subjective expected utility (SEU)-maximizing decision analysis. The fact that there are multiple stakeholders, not all of whom are alive at present, moves the decision problem from the domain of a single decision-maker to the less well-developed domain of multiple agents, for whom justice and cooperation over time in the absence of opportunities for explicit collaboration and agreement may be important. Even defining clearly what “optimize” means in such settings is difficult. At the individual level, what seems the best choice in retrospect may be very different from what seemed best in prospect, when decisions had to be made and when many possible futures were being considered. In retrospect, evaluations of alternatives can be powerfully affected by hindsight bias, regret, blame-seeking, availability bias, and other potent psychological influences on how we judge previous decisions (Kahneman, 2011). In prospect, our evaluations and judgments about what course of action seems best are influenced by different biases, including over-optimism, narrow framing, and over-confidence (ibid). Defining a single concept of “optimal” choice that satisfies the biases of both forward-looking and backward-looking evaluations may be impossible. At the group level, what most people prefer to do now may differ predictably from what most of them (or future generations) will later wish had been done now – and from what they may praise or blame current policy makers for doing or failing to do. Such differences can arise because of predictable shifts in beliefs and information, or from changes in tastes and preferences, as well as because of predictable differences in prospective and retrospective preferences and evaluations of alternatives.

The following sections present several frameworks for thinking constructively about how much we should invest in safety, resilient infrastructures and communities, precautionary measures against attacks or natural disasters, sustainable production and consumption practices and processes, and other instances of costly present care taken to create potential future risk-reducing benefits that will affect multiple generations. To simplify and clarify key issues, we first introduce simple, idealized models of multi-generational conflict and cooperation in the gradual consumption of a desirable resource, generically called “capital stock” or, more colloquially, “pie.” This can be variously interpreted to illuminate issues such as savings vs. investment in growth of capital stock in economic growth models; optimal consumption of a scarce resource that many generations would like to share (e.g., oil, or susceptibility of microbial pathogens to current antibiotics, or military reputation with allies and with enemies, etc.); investment in a stock of “safety” in infrastructure (e.g., fraction of bridges replaced or renewed no more than a target number of years ago, or height of a levee or sea wall to protect against flooding during extreme weather events); or investments in precaution against future disasters (e.g., stockpiling of antibiotics or other countermeasures). We consider how one might answer the ethical questions of how big a piece of the remaining pie each successive generation should take, and what duties each generation has to add to the stock of pie or capital, if doing so is possible but costly. This multi-generational sharing of a pie, and generalizations in which the size of the pie can change due to the production and consumption decisions of each generation, and perhaps to random events, provide fruitful metaphors for clarifying both economic and ethical aspects of intergenerational justice that arise in many practical applications, including decisions about how much each generation should spend to help reduce risks from natural disasters or terrorist attacks for future generations. We compare several principles and constructive analytic and ethical frameworks for deciding what each generation should do, addressing both what decisions should be made and how they should be made. Finally, the main generalizable insights and results from applying these frameworks to problems of intergenerational cooperation and justice are summarized, with attention to how they might be applied to improve practical decisions in which intergenerational consequences and justice are key concerns. In particular, we discuss implications for how to make ethically defensible investments in protecting against natural hazards, as well as implications for proposed principles of sustainable consumption and production of safety benefits.


Simple Models of Intergenerational Justice: Sharing a Pie over Time
An idealized model of intergenerational cooperation and decision-making is the following pie-division problem. At the start of the problem (conventionally labeled the beginning of period 1), the first generation is endowed with a pie of fixed size, conventionally normalized to be 1, or 100%. Members of that generation must decide how much of the pie to consume themselves, and how much to leave as a bequest to the next generation. Each successive generation in turn must then decide how much of the endowment of pie that it received from previous generations it will consume, and how much it will pass on to later generations. In the simplest case, the pie does not grow or shrink, except by the consumption decisions of each generation. Of course, generations may overlap, but the simplest models treat them as discrete; this does not substantially affect the analysis.

In variations of the problem, pie not consumed grows at some rate (analogous to savings and investment in economic growth models); or additions to the stock of pie may occur at random times (analogous to discoveries of new deposits of a non-renewable and valuable resource such as oil); or the pie may be perishable or may randomly shrink or disappear (analogous to depletion or exhaustion of a resource, or to random destruction of property by disasters). In each variation, the key question of how much to consume now remains. Especially instructive variations make explicit the possibility of two different types of investment for unconsumed pie: (a) Invest in growth (i.e., save some pie, which may then grow at a certain rate); or (b) Invest in safety, which reduces the amount of pie lost when disasters occur.


Analytic Frameworks for Managing Cooperation Across Generations
This section briefly introduces several different analytic frameworks for addressing the question of how much each generation should consume, save, and invest, allowing for the possibilities of investing in either growth (as in traditional economic models of optimal consumption and savings/investment over time) or in safety.
Economic Growth Models
For the past century, classical and neoclassical economic models of optimal capital accumulation and growth, such as the Ramsey (1928), Solow-Swan (1956), and Phelps (1961) models, have been used to answer questions about how best to manage a society’s consumption, savings, and investment over time. These models describe the changing stock of capital (or “pie”) over time by differential equations in continuous time or by difference equations in discrete time, such as
K(t + 1) = (1 + g)(1 – c)[1 – d(t)]K(t)
where K(t) is the stock of capital at the start of period t; g is the fractional growth rate for unconsumed capital (typically between about g = 0.02 and g = 0.10 per year); c is the consumption fraction (and therefore (1 – c) is the savings fraction, often denoted by s); and d(t) is the random fraction of capital lost in period t due to disasters. In classical economics, the capital good, K, is often interpreted as something like “corn” that can be either consumed, thereby producing immediate utility from consumption; or saved and invested (“planted”), in which case it will grow at rate g and expand future opportunities for consumption and savings/investment. In more elaborate models, the values of c and g may also vary over time. Traditional deterministic economic models of optimal consumption, savings, and growth do not model losses from disasters (in effect, assuming that all d(t) = 0), but do model labor supply and population growth, in addition to capital growth. Utility in period t is usually assumed to be based on the amount consumed then, cK(t). A central planner who wishes to maximize the net present value of utility (or, in some variations, the steady-state sustainable level of utility) can solve a dynamic optimization problem, constrained by the differential or difference equations for capital accumulation (and for growth in the population and labor force, if they are modeled), to obtain recommended levels of consumption, savings, and investment for each period (Ramsey, 1928). Extensions to stochastic growth models, in which the growth rate of unconsumed capital, g, varies randomly over time, have been developed and analyzed using techniques such as stochastic dynamic programming to illuminate the trade-offs between present and future consumption implied by different growth rates (or distributions of growth rates, if they are random) and polices (Olson, 2005).

Useful qualitative insights flow from such economic models, which characterize the set of possibilities for intergenerational choices and their probable consequences over time. Models of capital consumption and accumulation specify the physics, or rules of the game, within which intergenerational sharing of resources, consumption, and production take place. They also reveal qualitative properties of optimal policies. For example, analysis of growth models reveals conditions under which all optimal growth trajectories (i.e., sequences of states, consisting of consumption and savings/investment levels in each period, that jointly maximize discounted utility or similar objective functions) approach each other and stay close to each other along most of their lengths, regardless of the initial state. Such optimal growth path “turnpikes” exist for many deterministic and stochastic growth models. In simple models, the optimal policies have simple and intuitively appealing economic interpretations, with each period’s consumption and investment being optimized by adjusting consumption levels to equate the marginal utility from further current consumption to the discounted expected marginal value of further investment (i.e., the product of the marginal productivity of investment and the marginal utility from consuming the incremental output next period) (ibid).

Perhaps most interestingly, stochastic growth models reveal that there may be a critical threshold level of the initial capital stock above which it is guaranteed (with probability 1) that the optimal policy will never exhaust the capital stock, but below which there is a risk (or, if the growth rate g is variable enough, a certainty) that even optimal management will eventually end with K = 0 (economic collapse). Such results have implications for the management of fisheries and other renewable resources. If extinction is a realistic possibility, then keeping the stock above the threshold needed to avoid extinction might well be an overriding priority, trumping all other considerations about what each generation owes to future ones. Including the possibility of disasters in growth models (d(t) > 0) can modify optimal policies, e.g., by providing reason to restrict current consumption to provide an adequate margin of safety. For a non-renewable resource (i.e., growth rate g = 0), the optimal policy for sharing the initial stock among generations may shift toward more consumption earlier on if disaster might destroy some or all of the remaining stock. Whether such generalizations hold depends on details of the model considered, such as whether utility of consumption exhibits increasing or decreasing marginal utility (or some of each, perhaps being S-shaped, e.g., if consuming very little oil per generation has zero or little marginal utility compared to consuming more, but consuming a lot also generates less utility per barrel than consuming less). Likewise, incorporating disaster mitigation opportunities into a detailed model requires specifying the cost curve or technology possibilities for spending K(t) to reduce (shift leftward the distribution of) d(t), and how long the effects of such expenditures last. For example, investing in higher sea walls or levees consumes more of the current capital stock that might otherwise have been spent on consumption or invested in economic growth, but reduces the probable losses from floods during the useful life of the walls or levees. Understanding the relation between present costs and future benefits, as modeled by the leftward shift in the loss terms d(t) in future periods purchased by a current investment in safety, provides the essential technical information about possible costs and benefits of disaster risk reduction needed to decide what to do in a multi-period optimization model.

If the model includes population sizes and labor forces, and if a value function for reducing lives lost in the event of a disaster is included in the objective function (thus inviting the usual vexed questions about how to value statistical lives saved), then economic optimization models can deliver recommendations for consumption and investments (in growth and safety) in each period that take into account this evaluation of lives saved. The effects on optimized current consumption of allowing for potential disasters depend on model details; in various specific models, they range from consuming more now (“Get it while it lasts!”) to consuming less now in order to protect and expand future opportunities (“Safety first,” “Make hay while the sun shines,” i.e., invest while it is still productive to do so).If the objective function is smooth and exhibits diminishing marginal returns, then optimizing multi-period consumption, investment, and savings (e.g., via stochastic dynamic programming) typically requires equating the marginal returns from incremental expenditures of K(t) on present consumption, on savings and capital growth, and on disaster mitigation, assuming that future decisions will also be made optimally.



For our purposes of comparing different frameworks for making intergenerational consumption, growth, and safety (i.e., disaster mitigation) investment decisions, the point of including the random disaster term d(t) is not to study optimal growth policies in specific models, but only to point out that standard economic methods for studying optimal consumption and investment over time in models of capital and growth can easily be modified to investigate how the possibility of capital-destroying disasters – and of safety investments that mitigate tem – changes optimal policies. Overall, the possibility of investing in precautions that stochastically reduce the damage done by disasters (sacrificing some present consumption or investment in growth by instead spending some of K(t) to shift the distribution of d(t) leftward, toward smaller values) provides an alternative to savings and investment as a way to increase capital stock and production and consumption possibilities over time. Concerns for intergenerational justice are addressed only implicitly, by making decisions in each period, or for each generation, to maximize the objective function (e.g., expected discounted utility) for all. A fundamental limitation of all such models is that no single objective function may correctly represent the preferences of different generations, or even of social planners living at different times. Not only might future tastes and preferences for consumption vs. safety trade-offs and future societal attitudes toward accepting or mitigating disaster risks differ from present ones, but also future generations whose wellbeing is discounted in present objective functions might wish that a different objective function had been optimized. (Worse, if current choices about wealth vs. safety affect the existence or sizes of future generations, then the hypothetical preferences of potential future individuals might be considered to matter in deciding what should be done now. But the hypothetical preferences of as-yet non-existent individuals provides at best a speculative basis for making present choices.) Allowing different generations to have, and to act on, different objective functions from the current generation’s requires shifting our analytic perspective from multi-period economic optimization to game-theory to better understand how the choices of different generations interact over time.
Behavioral Game Theory Framework for Strategic Interactions among Generations
Game-theoretic frameworks for deciding how much of its inherited stock of goods each generation should allocate to consumption and how much it should bequeath to its successors via investments in disaster mitigation measures and economic growth differ radically from optimal economic growth models. They drop the fiction of a single dispassionate social planner who is willing and able to make decisions for each generation to maximize some overall objective function. The difference can be illustrated as follows. Suppose that the first generation, perhaps motivated by compassion or ethical considerations, intends to consume only a small share of the initial endowment of a non-renewable resource (“pie”), leaving the rest for posterity. If they somehow learned that the second generation plans to consume the entire remainder, passing nothing on, then generation 1 might be inclined to revise its initial generous intent, consuming more itself. But, if it turns out that generation 2’s intent to consume everything is based on discovering that generation 3 plans to consume whatever is bequeathed to it, passing nothing on, then generation 1 might feel that generation 2 is not so undeserving after all. In short, what each generation concludes that it should do might well depend on what it expects subsequent generations to do. If a generation trusts that a plan that it initiates for enriching the future will be followed faithfully by at least the next few generations, then it may bequeath more than if it lacks such trust.

How such trust arises is better illuminated by behavioral game theory, experimental economics, psychology, and descriptions of what is sometimes called “social capital” (trustworthiness of others with whom one participates in dealings) than by the logical prescriptions of formal game theory models, in which trust plays no role. Real people are often far more altruistic and cooperative than models of purely rational behaviors and interactions predict or explain. For example, in the much-studied dictator game, one player is given an amount of money (or other desirable good) to divide between himself and a second player. The recipient has all the power in this game, and might be expected to keep everything for himself. But this is not what is observed in many experimental dictator games and variations: most dictators choose to bequeath substantial shares (e.g., 20% or more) of the initial endowment to the other, powerless players, depending on what social norms are evoked by the contextual cues of the experiment, such as earning, sharing, pure giving, etc. (List, 2007). To what extent generous sharing is observed in practice depends on many contextual factors, such as whether participants view their interactions in a market frame or in a gift frame; on whether taking as well as giving is included in the feasible set of actions; on whether the player selected as the dictator believes that the choice reflects his own skill or luck in a fair contest; on how often the situation is repeated. But purely selfish behavior is seldom observed (List, 2007). The multi-generation division of an initial endowment can be viewed as an expansion and generalization of the dictator game in which each generation is in the position of the dictator in deciding how much to share with powerless future generations.



Although behavioral game theory and experiments provides insights into realistic behaviors that formal non-cooperative game theory (e.g., based on the understanding that all rational players will use subgame perfect equilibrium (SPE) strategies if they exist and are unique) cannot, neither type of analysis is concerned primarily with clarifying what choices are most morally correct. Behavioral game theory and behavioral economics recognize that people (and some other primates) have intuitive and emotional responses to perceived fairness, equity, injustice, reciprocity, and altruism that are important drivers of decisions about when and how much to share in a variety of settings, including the dictator game and its variants. These personal moral intuitions and impulses are tremendously important in helping real people to cooperate more successfully than purely rational (SPE-implementing) agents can in many situations (e.g., one-shot and iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma, the stag game, the centipede game, the trust game, and other staples of modern game theory). Yet, they do not provide a coherent normative account of applied social or moral decision-making that can be used to obtain reliable moral guidance on important policy questions, such as how best to share the burdens and benefits of investments in disaster mitigation and in economic growth across generations. To the contrary, our moral intuitions are easily dumbfounded when situations appeal to several competing moral intuitions (as in the trolley track problem, or in alternative framings of tax breaks for dependents as providing disproportionate benefits to the wealthy, if they are used; or as imposing disproportionate costs on the wealthy, if they are not). Likewise, the prescriptions from formal mathematical non-cooperative game theory models of interacting rational players (or generations, in our setting) are not intended to convey any moral authority: SPE solutions and refinements only guarantee that no player can get more of what it wants by changing its strategy, and not that what any player wants is morally worthwhile.
Axiomatic Solution Concepts from Cooperative Game Theory
A different branch of game theory concerns itself directly with normative principles that participants in a cooperative enterprise might adopt to decide how to share the benefits from cooperation. This is axiomatic game theory, which defines and studies the logical relations among solution concepts in cooperative games, such as those involving bargaining or fair division of one or more goods. For example, the Shapley value, which assigns to each player the expected incremental value that the player creates by joining a coalition of other players (when the order in which the players join is random), is the unique way to allocate gains from cooperation that satisfies certain axioms, such as that players be treated symmetrically, without favoritism (each player’s allocation depends only on what it contributes, and not on who the player is) and that the allocation procedure should be Pareto-efficient, allocating 100% of the potential gains from cooperation. The Nash Bargaining solution, which maximizes the product of the utility gains of the players compared the no-agreement outcome, is likewise the unique solution concept satisfying these two conditions and the additional two that the outcome should not depend on the arbitrary choice of scales for expressing player utilities, and that expanding the opportunity set of utilities jointly available to the players by introducing new options should either leave the original outcome unchanged, or change it to one of the newly added options. Each of these and many other proposed solution concepts for sharing in the cooperative production and allocation of desired outcomes, can be justified as the unique concept implied by a set of more-or-less reasonable-seeming normative axioms, many of which directly represent principles of fairness such as symmetry (i.e., no favoritism), or maximizing the minimum payoff among players), as well as Pareto efficiency.

However, axiomatic cooperative game theory is vulnerable to its own version of moral dumbfounding: different proposed normative principles can conflict logically. This leads to impossibility theorems showing that no possible decision procedure can satisfy all the appealing principles (normative axioms) that one might want to require. For example, the Shapley value solution and the Nash Bargaining solution can prescribe different outcomes for the same situation, so that no outcome satisfies the normative principles proposed for both. In such cases, one might try to decide which principles should be sacrificed so that other (mutually consistent) ones can be preserved, or, equivalently, choose among alternative solution concepts. But there is no meta-ethical framework within axiomatic game theory to prescribe or justify which normative principles to keep and which to abandon when there are logical conflicts among them. Axiomatic theories may also under-determine outcomes in practice. For example, the Nash bargaining solution requires knowing what the disagreement outcome is, but it is not always clear how it should be determined, e.g., as the present status quo, which may incorporate the results of many historical injustices, or as an idealized initial position that treats all participants symmetrically. Such questions about how one should, even in principle, implement the prescriptions of normative axiomatic solution concepts, open a gap between their mathematical implications and the information needed to act on them. Theories of justice developed by Rawls and his successors can help to close this gap by specifying a particular initial position from which (idealized, hypothetical) deliberation and selection of principles proceeds. They also provide a meta-ethical framework for reasoning about how societies should choose among rival normative principles (e.g., among different axiomatic cooperative game-theoretic solution concepts) to guide their subsequent applied choices and the rights, duties, and principles of fair distribution or redistribution over time that they should impose on themselves and on each other. These theories are explained next.


Intergenerational Justice
Philosophical discussions of intergenerational justice since Rawls (2001) have considered an idealized form of social contracting across generations. Participants from all generations are imagined to jointly agree on policies for sharing resources and investments over time, such as social savings rates, from a hypothetical “original position” behind a “veil of ignorance,” in which no participant knows which generation (or other position within society) he or she will be born into (e.g., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2008; Manzini et al., 2010). Principles that would be agreed to from behind this veil of ignorance are defined as just principles, to which real policy-makers should adhere if they see to make just decisions. This concept can be applied to inform each generation’s consumption and investment decisions, including decisions about how much to consume and how much to invest in disaster mitigation and community resilience, or directly in economic growth, at different times. In the simple case of sharing a non-renewable resource (“pie”) over time for a finite number of generations (which may be random, if the duration of the human race is uncertain), the allocation of the resource across generations recommended by such a Rawlsian criterion typically coincides with the allocation that would be achieved by social utility maximization in growth economics, but the two may differ when production is possible (Llavadoet al., 2010)

Identifying just policies as those that would result from social contracting if all stakeholders started from a symmetric original position solves the problem of having earlier generations exploit their asymmetrically powerful position to the detriment of later generations, e.g., by consuming all of the initial stock of pie immediately. Because participants in the multi-generation social contract arrived at from the original position do not know which generation they will occupy, they are motivated to treat all generations fairly. This framework for intertemporal justice also provides an alternative to discounting, thus avoiding the ethical problem posed by conventional discounting in cost-benefit analysis of under-weighting the costs and benefits borne by far-future generations compared to those borne by present or near-future generations (van Liedekerke, 2004; Parfit, 1982). From the original position, the interests of different generations are valued equally, and so any discounting would reflect only real asymmetries, such as in production opportunities (e.g., earlier investments in growth pay off over more years), and not a bias against later generations.

Other proposed features of intergenerational justice have been erected on these foundations by speculating about what people in the original position would agree to. Rawls himself argued that the primary duty of each generation is to bequeath just institutions to the next; once this has been fulfilled (via an “accumulation phase”), a frequently proposed secondary duty is that each generation should pass on to the next an endowment at least equivalent (in size or productivity) to the one it received, so that no generation’s consumption reduces the opportunities or wellbeing of those that follow. However, such proposed principles of sustainability in consumption and production invite scrutiny and skepticism (e.g., Wolf, 2007), especially if they are asserted without careful qualification and reference to specific underlying economic growth models. For example, in the case of an initial endowment of pie that can only be consumed, and not produced, requiring that no generation’s consumption should diminish the stock bequeathed to future generations would imply that none of the pie would ever be consumed – a Pareto-inefficient outcome that would not necessarily appeal to anyone, even behind the veil of ignorance. Similarly, for a model of multi-generational sharing of a renewable resource, Kraukraemer and Batina (1999) show that imposing a sustainability constraint of non-decreasing utility over time creates Pareto-inefficient stockpiling of the resource: everyone would prefer a usage pattern that allowed later generations to have lower utilities than earlier ones. Such conflicts between various proposed criteria for sustainability and what all members of all generations would prefer arise in many other models of intergenerational sharing (e.g., Hoberg and Baumgartner, 2011), although not in all if there is no uncertainty and if property rights, taxes, and transfer payments among generations are dexterously deployed to allow earlier generations to, in effect, purchase resource usage rights from later ones (Howarth and Norgaard, 1990). But the frequent conflicts between sustainability principles and economic efficiency (e.g., what is unanimously preferred by all members of all generations) are perhaps also unsurprising from the perspective of a Rawlsian account of distributive justice, insofar as social contracting from an original position in which no participant knows what generation he or she will occupy removes any reason to favor the utility or opportunities of later generations over those of earlier ones.

Despite their considerable intellectual appeal, theories of intergenerational justice based on implicit social contracting behind a veil of ignorance are not free of philosophical and logical difficulties. For example, in such theories, it is not always clear how potential future people whose very existence may be affected by present production and consumption decisions should be treated (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2008). Llavador et al. (2010) present models in which the possible extinction of humanity is considered as a key uncertainty about the future. They prove that it is optimal, in economic growth models with a policy objective of maximizing the minimum welfare across generations, weighted by the sizes of future populations (so that potential individuals, rather than entire discrete generations, are treated as the participants in the social contract) to ignore this uncertainty about continued survival in deciding how best to allocate consumption and investment over time. This result holds when the economy is sufficiently productive. In effect, the appropriate discount rate due to uncertainty about continued existence is then zero.



Likewise, if future people will have habits, expectations, and preferences that are shaped in part by current production and consumption decisions, then it may not be clear what preferences should be assumed in modeling what they would agree to in the original position. For example, if early generations derive high utility from oil consumption, and if later generations will regard oil consumption as an unattractive addiction that thankfully became obsolete when depletion of oil forced discovery of more attractive alternatives, then a Rawlsian social contract that allowed members of different generations to bring these preferences with them behind the veil of ignorance (but not knowledge of who would be in which generation) might lead to the conclusion that early consumption of oil was just. But if more gradual consumption of oil would lead to all generations putting a high value on it, then these different assumed preferences might imply that gradual consumption was the just pattern. If each alternative choice about patterns of production, consumption, and investment over time induces the generation-specific preferences needed to justify it (by making it the alternative that would be selected from the original position), then the original position loses its prescriptive power.
Sustainability, Protective Principles, and Fundamental Trade-offs
Sustainability principles, usually requiring that resources or opportunities or utilities be non-decreasing over time (Wolf, 2007), are intended to make sure that current policies do not unjustly sacrifice the interests of powerless future generations in favor of the interests of present generations who currently have the power to make choices. Other approaches have the same goal of protecting the interests of future generations in current decision-making; these range from variations on Rawls's idealized social contracting (Van Liederkerke, 2004) to idealized Nash bargaining solutions in which each generation is assumed to be given the power to veto plans that it considers unacceptable (Manzini et al., 2010). In addition, some optimal growth models imply a sustainability condition, in which, in steady state, each generation passes on to the next the capital that it received from its predecessor, and this stock is maintained at a level that maximizes the utility from consumption per capita for members of each generation (Phelps, 1961). However, when realistic uncertainties about future preferences and choice sets and about the consequences of current decisions are taken into account, the capacity of current decision-makers to protect the interests of future generations effectively may be very limited. For example, Krysiak and Collado (2009) present models in which there is a trade-off between taking actions to protect future generations against risks and taking actions that all generations prefer, while Hoberg and Baumgartner (2011) demonstrate similar trade-offs between sustainability and efficiency when irreversible policy decisions are made by earlier generations, trying to protect the interests of later ones, but later generations have better information about the (perhaps unforeseen and unintended) consequences of earlier policies.

More generally, sustainable production and consumption, economic efficiency (i.e., Pareto optimality), Rawlsian justice, and free democratic (non-dictatorial) choice procedures have all been proposed as desirable principles for guiding and constraining how societies should make decisions, both within and across generations. But careful analysis indicates that any two of these principles, when appropriately formalized for specific models relating choices to economic growth, can conflict. For example, free democratic choice procedures may lead to outcomes that no one favors, e.g., if different people have different beliefs about the probable consequences of alternative choices, and these probabilistic beliefs are used to help select policies (Nehring, 2005). Similarly, conflicts between sustainability criteria and Pareto-efficiency (Wolf, 2007; Hoberg and Baumgartner, 2011) and trade-offs between Pareto-efficiency and various measures of intergenerational equity or justice in resource allocations arise for many intergenerational decision processes (e.g., Krysiak and Collado, 2009). No matter how well intended, efforts to protect the interests of future generation using the information available today risks creating outcomes that, in retrospect, no one favors; this is especially likely if today’s choices have uncertain, irreversible consequences and if future preferences are uncertain (Hoberg and Baumgartner, 2011). Thus, fundamental tradeoffs must be made among these proposed desirable characteristics of collective choice procedures for managing the distribution of pie or other goods over time and generations. Equivalently, impossibility theorems expressing the logical incompatibility of different sets of principles under stated conditions limit the possibilities for a satisfactory approach to intergenerational cooperation.


Investing in Building Resilient Communities and Societies: An Emerging Framework
If the normative frameworks and principles for intergenerational justice we have considered so far – growth economics, behavioral game theory, axiomatic solution concepts for cooperative games, philosophical theories of intergenerational justice, and proposed principles of sustainability and protection of the interests of future generation – all lead to contradictions or unresolved difficulties, then what type of analysis might be used instead to provide practical guidance on how much to spend on consumption, investments in disaster mitigation, and investments in economic growth in each period? One emerging approach avoids such mathematical and theoretical arguments, instead emphasizing building the capacity of communities and societies to respond quickly and competently to new information and circumstances as they arise. This is the framework of resilience for communities and societies; it is still under development by many investigators. Key concepts are that resilient communities should prepare to manage disasters effectively by accumulating the physical and social capitals needed to adapt and respond effectively and to manage mitigation and recovery efforts when needed (Tierney, 2013). Physical capitals include transportation, telecommunications, power, and emergency medical infrastructures. Social capitals include training and preparation, ability of communities to organize effectively and act competently and autonomously when needed, self-reliant communities, and high trust and individual trustworthiness in cooperating to respond to disasters. Proponents of resilience often argue that communities and societies benefit in multiple ways from developing the capacity, responsibility, and self-reliance needed to improvise and take appropriate actions to deal with possibly unforeseen events. From this perspective, the obligation of each generation to the next may be viewed as bequeathing at least a minimal level of resilience, including the needed physical and social capitals.

Resilience frameworks are still a work in progress. They are sometimes conflated with proposed principles of sustainability, participatory decision-making, environmental justice, environmentalism, putative rights to safety and prosperity, and intergenerational equity for managing interlinked social-economic-ecological systems, often with little explicit discussion of the limitations, trade-offs, and contradictions among the principles espoused (e.g., www.riskinstitute.org/peri/images/file/HDR.pdf). Even without such overlays, however, it is useful to keep in mind the basic idea that investment in building community resilience may be a valuable alternative or complement to investments in economic growth or direct protective measures (e.g., better levees) when the possibility of occasional disasters is present.


Ethical Frameworks
Questions about how people should treat each other – including others remote in time or in space who are affected by our choices – have long been addressed by ethical theories. Several are reflected in the preceding frameworks. In brief, utilitarianism and consequentialism are embodied in optimal growth models that choose each period’s consumption and investment levels (in growth, safety, resilience, etc.) to maximize a multi-generation social utility function. Deontological ethical theories are reflected in prescriptive models of intergenerational justice, where the implied duty for each generation is to do what is just, such as making investments to maximize the average or minimum utility over all current and future generations (when all others do the same), depending on what rules one believes would be adopted behind the veil of ignorance. Some advocates of sustainability suggest that each generation has a moral duty to invest enough to provide for non-decreasing social utility, opportunities, or resources for future generations. In some simple deterministic models, utilitarian, just duty-based, and intergenerational equity-based prescriptions coincide, as when all three prescribe treating the next generation (via investment in capital stock) as one would want to be treated by the previous generation – a formulation of the “golden rule” for optimal growth that maximizes steady-state (sustainable) utility from consumption (Phelps, 1961). Virtue ethics is reflected in emerging ideas about resilient communities that identify development of resilience with cultivation of private and social virtues such as preparation and prudence, self-reliance, responsibility, trustworthiness even under stress, and capacity to respond to crises competently, cooperatively, and creatively when needed. Thus, the frameworks that we have discussed may be viewed as building on major ethical principles, perhaps helping to move them closer to practical applications in managing intergenerational risks and investment decisions.
Yüklə 12,64 Mb.

Dostları ilə paylaş:
1   ...   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57




Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©genderi.org 2024
rəhbərliyinə müraciət

    Ana səhifə