Microsoft Word goedel-duzi rtf



Yüklə 246,82 Kb.
Pdf görüntüsü
səhifə10/11
tarix01.08.2018
ölçüsü246,82 Kb.
#60063
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   10   11

 

18

Denoting 



Ref(T)

 the set of all the sentences refutable in the theory T (i.e. the set of all the 

sentences 

ϕ such that T |– ¬ϕ), it is obvious that also this set 

Ref(T)

 is not recursive. Now we 



can illustrate mutual relations between the sets 

Thm(T)


Th(N)


, and 

Ref(T)


 by the following 

figure


22

 



 

 

 



 

 

 



 

If the (consistent) theory T is recursively axiomatized and complete, the sets 

Thm(T), 

Th(N)


 coincide, and 

Ref(T)


 is a complement of them. 

Another consequence of the Incompleteness theorem is the undecidability of the problem 

of logical truth: The FOPL proof calculus is a theory without special axioms. Though it is a 

complete calculus (all the logically valid formulas are provable), as an “empty” theory it is 



not decidable: there is no algorithm that would decide any formula 

ϕ whether it is a theorem 

or not (which equivalently means whether it is a logically valid formula or not). The problem 

of logical truth is not decidable in FOPL. For, Q is an adequate theory with a finite number of 

axioms. If Q

1

,…Q


7

 are its axioms (closed formulas), then a sentence 

ϕ is provable in Q iff  

(Q

1



 & … & Q

7



→ ϕ is provable in the FOPL calculus

23

, and so (Q



1

 & … & Q


7

→ ϕ is a 



logically valid formula. If the calculus were decidable so would be Q, which is not. 

Alonzo Church proved that the proof calculus is partially decidable: there is an algorithm

which at an input formula 

ϕ that is  logically valid outputs the answer Yes.  If however the 

input formula 

ϕ is not a logical truth the algorithm may answer no or it can never output any 

answer. 

Gödel discovered that the sentence 

ν claiming “I am not provable” is equivalent to the 

sentence 

τ claiming “There is no <ϕ> such that both <ϕ> and <¬ϕ> are in 

Thm(T)


”. The 

latter is a formal statement that the system is consistent. Since 

ν  is not provable, and ν and τ 

are equivalent, 

τ is not provable as well. Thus we have: 

Gödel’s Second Theorem on incompleteness. In any consistent recursively axiomatizable 

theory T that is strong enough to encode sequences of numbers (and thus the syntactic notions 

of “formula”, “sentence”, “proof”) the consistency of the theory T is not provable in T. 

The second incompleteness theorem shows that there is no hope of proving, e.g., the 

consistency of the first-order arithmetic using finitist means provided we accept that finitist 

means are correctly formalized in a theory the consistency of which is provable in PA. As 

Georg Kreisel remarked, it would actually provide no interesting information if a theory T 

proved its consistency. This is because inconsistent theories prove everything, including their 

consistency. Thus a consistency proof of T in T would give us no clue as to whether T really 

is consistent.  

                                                 

22

 See Švejdar 2002  



23

 Here we use a Theorem of deduction: Q

1

 & … & Q


n

 |

− ϕ iff Q



1

 & … & Q


n-1

 |

− Q



n

 

→ ϕ 



Axioms 

Thm(T) Th(N) 

Ref(T) 



 

19

One of the first to recognize the revolutionary significance of the incompleteness results 



was John von Neumann (Hungarian-born brilliant mathematician) who even almost 

anticipated Gödel’s second  theorem on incompleteness. Others were slower to absorb the 

essence of the problem and to accept its solution. For example, Hilbert’s assistant Paul 

Bernays had difficulties with technicalities

24

 of the proof that were cleared up only after 



repeated correspondence. Gödel’s breakthrough even drew sharp criticism, which was due to 

prevailing conviction that mathematical thinking can be captured by laws of pure symbol 

manipulation, and due to inability to make the necessary distinctions involved, such as that 

between the notion of truth  and  proof. Thus, for instance, the famous set-theorist Ernst 

Zermelo interpreted the latter in a way that leads to a pure contradiction with Gödel’s results. 

3.2. Research after Gödel    

Let me close this section by making a remark that Gödel incompleteness theorems, 

especially the celebrated 2

nd

 Incompleteness Theorem, not only is a brilliant result which 



logicians are proud of and which can be reflected philosophically; it also plays the role of a 

useful technical tool for proving theorems about meta-mathematics of axiomatic theories. 

Therefore I would like to mention the fact that an interesting research inspired by Gödel 

continued also after Gödel

25



Since no reasonable axiomatic theory T can prove its own consistency, a theory S capable 



of proving the consistency of T can be viewed as considerably stronger than T. Of course, 

considerably stronger implies non-equivalent. The Levy Reflection Principle, which is non-

trivial but also not so difficult to prove, says that Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory ZF proves 

consistency of each of its finitely axiomatized sub-theories. So by Gödel 2

nd

 Incompleteness 



Theorem, full ZF is considerably stronger than any of its finitely axiomatized fragments. This 

in turn yields a simple proof that ZF is not finitely axiomatizable. The same, with a similar 

but a little bit more complicated proof, is true of PA. Also ZF proves the consistency of PA. 

As to the research after Gödel, I want to mention the Gentzen consistency proof, Pudlak’s 

extensions of Gödel 2

nd

 Incompleteness Theorem and the connections of Gödel Theorem to 



modal logic.  

Gerhard Gentzen, around 1940, raised the following question: once we know that 

consistency of Peano arithmetic PA cannot be proved in PA itself but can be proved in ZF, 

what exactly of all the set-theoretical machinery is necessary to prove consistency of PA? 

Gentzen’s answer was: all we need is to know that the (countable) ordinal 

ε

0



, defined as the 

limit or ordinals 1, 

ω, ω

ω

, ... is well founded, i.e., it is not a majorant of an infinite decreasing 



sequence of ordinals.  

Pavel Pudlak in 1980’s showed that Gödel 2

nd

 Incompleteness Theorem holds 



also for very weak fragments of PA, and if carefully (re)formulated, it holds for the 

Robinson’s arithmetic too. He also proved a quantitative version of Gödel 2

nd

 Incompleteness 



Theorem, saying that statements of the form "there is no proof of contradiction the length of 

which is less than n”, while provable in T if T satisfies usual requirements, only have proofs 

the lengths of which grow very rapidly with n.  

Provability logic is a modal propositional logic where the usual modal operator   (Box) is 

interpreted as formal provability in some fixed axiomatic theory extending arithmetic. Then 

e.g. 


¬ False (not provable False) is a modal formula which can be read “contradiction is 

unprovable in T”. Its arithmetical counterpart is the formalized consistency statement which, 

by Gödel 2nd Incompleteness Theorem, cannot be proved in T. So 

¬ False is an example of 

                                                 

24

 The technical device used in the proof is now known as Gödel numbering 



25

 These remarks were formulated by Vítězslav Švejdar. I am deeply grateful for them. 




Yüklə 246,82 Kb.

Dostları ilə paylaş:
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   10   11




Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©genderi.org 2024
rəhbərliyinə müraciət

    Ana səhifə